Regulation by Enforcement

An increasingly common response by regulators to what they view as undesirable market trends or challenges has been a sharp turn toward litigation to introduce novel legal theories and frameworks that could have been the product or subject of legislative or administrative rulemaking. The decision to do so has been met by calls claiming such administrative action to be unfair, and in some instances, illegal.

This Article revisits the New Deal origins of regulation by enforcement, and its more recent incarnations, and explains that as a legal matter, regulators generally enjoy discretion as to whether to make policy through rulemaking, adjudication, or by filing a lawsuit in federal court. However, there are some exceptions to this principle, as well as some reasons to believe that recent doctrinal developments hostile to agency adjudications could reduce the discretion of agencies to choose their policymaking tool, especially when their actions are understood to be naked attempts to grab turf or circumvent democratic norms embedded in the Administrative Procedure Act. In this Article, we analyze the incentives facing agencies when choosing to regulate by enforcement, consider some of the new risks, and lay out a framework for thinking about when agencies should regulate by rule, and when they should regulate by enforcement.

INTRODUCTION

One visible response by regulators to what they view as persistent—or particularly fast-moving—market challenges has been a sharp turn toward litigation to introduce or test out novel legal theories and frameworks that could have been the product or subject of legislative or administrative rulemaking. This approach, popularly termed “regulation by enforcement,” prompted fierce critiques from commentators and the marketplace, often from the standpoint of fairness—and based on an implicit assumption that such regulatory conduct might be illegal, or at the very least, politically motivated. In response, defenders of agency action have called the criticisms “bogus,” “misguided,” and lambasted politicians, market participants and even academics, for uttering the phrase.

In this Article, we work to give substance to what is all too often a nebulous term of art. In Part I, we provide an overview of how this particular species of regulatory intervention—visible across multiple issue areas such as the oversight of cryptocurrencies, environmental and social governance (“ESG”), insider trading and antitrust—tests certain assumptions about the nature of the administrative state. Specifically, we show that the work of regulatory agencies is traditionally understood as consisting of creative and destructive functions, mapped along axes of rulemaking and enforcement, respectively. Rulemaking by enforcement, however, blurs the lines between the two, both disrupting and supplementing the rulemaking toolkit. Thus, while creating important opportunities for advancing regulatory priorities, it invariably raises normative questions about its appropriateness as a matter of legal and historical precedence.

In Part II, we take a closer look into rationales explaining why a regulator might choose to create policy by means of enforcement rather than through more traditional rulemaking. To begin, we first identify what “regulation by enforcement” has meant historically, starting with key precedent and decisions introduced at the twilight of the New Deal era, and moving toward more recent iterations in the last quarter century. Next, we identify what can be understood as a spectrum of possible incentives and motivations behind regulation by enforcement. These range from the necessary—where agencies act because they have no other option, such as when notice-and-comment rulemaking is not possible owing to the absence of clear legislative authority—to the optional, where regulation by enforcement (rather than detailed rulemaking) offers a faster or more expedient pathway to exercise or expand oversight. Underlying these motives driving regulation by enforcement, we highlight opportunities for regulators to achieve a variety of laudable goals, such as promoting the realization of their institutional missions, delivering desirable marketplace outcomes in relatively expeditious ways, and offering a statement of intent on the part of authorities about preferred policy positions in a manner designed to arrest misconduct before it can wreak actual damage. However, we also point out other less savory possible incentives to pursuing rulemaking through enforcement, as opposed to through administrative processes, including an interest in reducing or circumventing the transparency and accountability intended by traditional administrative processes, and extending an agency’s authority in ways that might otherwise be impermissible, politically costly or even illegal.

In Part III, we investigate the legality of regulation by enforcement and explore these trade-offs in greater depth. In analyzing applicable case-law, we suggest that its legality is more complicated than scholars and commentators might appreciate. On the surface, the strategy of regulation by enforcement is perfectly legal and stands on solid legal ground—well within the authorization afforded to agencies by governing case law. Looking deeper, however, courts have been silent on a more fundamental question: whether regulation by enforcement is legal when it involves more than filling gaps in administrative and legislative dictates, and it is used as a substitute for detailed rulemaking or, even more extreme, in a way designed to undermine the procedural safeguards put in place to ensure informed rulemaking. With this in mind, Part III then moves to examine the appropriateness (rather than just the legality) of regulation by enforcement. Here, the Article inspects under what circumstances this regulatory strategy is (and is not) in line with normative rule-of-law values that underpin the administrative state, as well as expectations that rulemaking be informed and loyal to the values of legitimacy and procedural fairness.

We observe that regulation by enforcement can enable regulators to achieve a range of positive outcomes. It gives agencies teeth to promote their institutional mandates and to generate confidence among the public that the agency is, in fact, doing the job it is charged to do. Regulation by enforcement can thus create efficiencies in agency administration when it produces sought-after policy results (for example, improved investor protections, more competitive markets) at relatively lower bureaucratic cost (for example, with greater speed and encompassing fewer procedural steps). On the other hand, the strategy can also come with notable shortcomings. When enforcement attempts to circumvent longstanding norms of procedural fairness, informed rulemaking, deliberative analysis, and the quality of the policymaking can be diminished, with lower informational content, shallower expertise, and limited public engagement underlying decision-making. Regulatory effects may be scattershot, where high-profile actions target certain actors but leave others alone. These procedural and outcomes-driven effects can mean that regulation by enforcement can end up suffering from a perception of limited legitimacy, increasing the reputational risks to agencies, as well as raising the critique that agency action may be excessively political and not grounded in the rule of law. Regulatory agencies thus risk being viewed as less technocratic and expert and driven more by selfish, rather than public interests. In such cases, concerns can filter into the judicial review mechanism, and ambitious attempts to engage in regulation by enforcement can run around in which courts rule against the government’s position—or even more dramatically, roll back the general authority being asserted by the litigating agency.

Against this backdrop, this Article provides a framework for understanding regulation by enforcement, and examines the historical precedent, legal basis, and tradeoffs that undergird the practice. Throughout, we recognize the complexity of agency decision-making, tasked with maintaining stability, integrity, as well as entrepreneurialism within the market. Our Article situates regulation by enforcement as part of a spectrum of tools deployed by regulators looking to fulfill the demands of their institutional mandates, within tight budgets and under the eye of political critics and an engaged public. As such, the strategy comes with a number of significant advantages and benefits. But it also presents notable risks and costs for advocates of governmental authority, especially given recent Supreme Court decisions on separation of powers jurisprudence that have privileged settled expectations as a check on regulatory innovation. Rather than taking a particular side—and seeking to overcome the ideological tensions that have polarized discussion on this topic—we offer an account that highlights the legal and normative trade-offs involved, in a bid to contribute to a more thoroughgoing understanding of regulation by enforcement as an administrative phenomenon of the 21st century regulatory state.

I.  THE RULEMAKING/ADJUDICATION DICHOTOMY

The modern regulatory agency has two principal ways to make policy with the force of law. It can promulgate rules of prospective application and general applicability that interpret the statutory authority given to it by Congress. This is defined in the Administrative Procedure Act as “rulemaking,” and almost always takes the form of “notice and comment” or “informal” rulemaking. Alternatively, it can enforce those rules, and its other statutory authorities, through adjudications pursued either through administrative adjudicatory proceedings or by filing suit in federal court—or through informal settlement negotiations with entities charged with illegal conduct. In this section, we describe the basic implications and processes required to engage in rulemaking and adjudication. We then illustrate them with some examples from the SEC’s halting efforts to regulate cryptocurrencies, which have been undertaken largely through enforcement actions that are adjudicated either by agency officials or in the federal courts, rather than through rulemaking. In the following section we consider some of the incentives the agency must consider when it decides how, exactly, it should make policy—and what the tradeoffs are of making policy through adjudication—that is, by suing the entities that it regulates, rather than via the rulemaking process.

Conceptually, rulemaking and adjudication are distinct exercises. Rulemaking can be understood as a “creative act.” It might be analogized to legislation—or at least “legislation” in an agency-specific area subject to a particular set of procedural requirements. When Congress passes statutes, it is making laws of prospective application and general applicability, as opposed to a backwards-looking individualized determination. When making rules, agencies are doing the same thing. Regulatory agencies embark on a process that is intended to be both open to public observation and comment, and that is conducted on the basis of the expertise that the agency can mobilize in developing the rule, both from resources developed within the agency, and from whatever knowledge that can be harnessed outside of it. The agency drafts the rule, publicizes the proposal, seeks and responds to public comment from interested parties, revises the rule, obtains approval for promulgation from the political leaders of the agency, and then publishes the final rule, making it subject to judicial review.

Policymaking through enforcement, by contrast, can be interpreted as more of a “destructive” act. Successful agency litigation stops conduct by a regulated industry, through a cease-and-desist order, for example, a censure, license suspension, or fine. It imposes sanctions in most cases in which the agency wins in court. Agency adjudication is the administrative law version of a judicial proceeding—it looks backwards at conduct that has already occurred and, if it concludes that the conduct violated the law, it imposes penalties. As with a judicial proceeding, adjudication begins with an investigation by the agency’s personnel, and then the filing of a lawsuit or an administrative proceeding. The government and the defendants then participate in a process of discovery (usually very limited in the administrative law context), briefings, arguments, and a decision rendered old by an adjudicator as to whether a violation has in fact occurred.

As a general heuristic, “rulemaking” refers to an action when an agency behaves like a legislature, and “adjudication” occurs when it acts like a court. However, there are complications. Enforcement through adjudication can take place in courts of law, or in in-house administrative proceedings run by agency officials, the administrative law judges who preside over formal adjudications, or the myriad other kinds of agency judges who decide various kinds of agency adjudications. And, of course, it can take place through settled enforcement actions. In such cases, the agency is not acting like a court at all, but rather like a prosecutor extracting a plea deal, at times before even bringing a charge.

Crucially, policymaking for the future—which is ultimately, the point of rulemaking—can also take on guises that escape simple dichotomies. In other words, agencies can exercise authority through a sophisticated, “softer” range of levers that, while carrying persuasive and expressive power, wield lesser formal intensity and legal obligation than notice-and-comment rulemaking or adjudication. Agencies can spotlight their positions using mechanisms like no-action and exemptive letters, interpretative guidance, and even press releases and public statements. Interpretations of law, and in the case of no action letters, the application of law to specific facts—while avoiding the process of rulemaking—can set expectations and impact market behavior. At the same time, such intermediate measures do not possess the hard finality offered by rulemaking or enforcement. Agency staff can always reconsider positions taken in the letters and adjust course (and even abandon it) when necessary. Indeed, verbiage accompanying such letters makes clear that staff disseminating them speak only for themselves, and not the agency as a whole.

Moreover, adjudication can involve the application of law to facts in a way that can result in new interpretations with binding effect on how the law is pertains to like circumstances, effectively creating prescriptive direction for regulators and industry alike. Adjudication can, in the process, draw on the soft law tools noted above, like staff guidance or answers to frequently asked questions, all the way to previous formal rulemaking, to create new support structures for the law that themselves carry legal effect. Similarly, even findings of fact—like whether certain behavior meets a condition precedent for establishing an illegal act or violation of the law—may involve interpreting and expanding black-letter legal requirements, even as fact-finding ordinarily ranks as the least law-oriented task of an adjudicator.

Securities law offers no shortage of examples illustrating just how consequentially law making can be performed by adjudicators. In what is widely considered to be the most important case for establishing the perimeter of securities law, SEC v. W. J. Howey Co., the Supreme Court (not Congress) defined the bedrock concept of an “investment contract”—a “catch-all” type of “security” falling outside of more traditional categories (for example a stock or a bond). Drawing on prior judicial interpretations of states’ Blue Sky Laws, Howey laid out a broad set of standards with which the SEC would, quite literally, prosecute the shifting parameters of its authority for the next eight decades. The 1946 case, which concerned real estate transactions involving orange groves in Florida, declared that an investment contract arises where there is (i) an investment of money; (ii) in a common enterprise; (iii) for profit; and (iv) derived from the efforts of others. This court-created framework was intended to anchor a facts-and-circumstances based analysis, and was flexible enough to apply to situations in which investor-risks arose from novel or new financing arrangements. But in detailing these four prongs in 1946, even the Supreme Court could not have possibly imagined the sheer range of schemes and assets to which the Howey test would eventually be applied, from animal breeding arrangements to contracts for death benefits. Invariably, these individual requirements have each been subject to a multitude of interpretations over time as Howey prongs have been thoroughly litigated by parties contesting the ambit of the market’s regulatory perimeter—and whether a particular kind of issuer should be included, or not.

To take one example, the Howey Court itself left unresolved how the common enterprise prong should be interpreted. In other words, it did not lay out specific and exclusive criteria to define what a common enterprise should be, and the elements needed to constitute one. To fill this gap, the lower courts have created different tests for the type and intensity of “common enterprise” required to be found to establish that a contract is an investment contract subject to SEC oversight. In Howey, the common enterprise could be found through the service contract, which gave the servicer “full and complete” possession of the land specified in the contract, and permitted the servicer to pool the investors’ money and to then distribute returns from selling oranges to them on a pro rata basis in accordance with their contribution. In this scenario, the Howey contract purchasers enjoyed so-called “horizontal commonality” with one another, as the returns to the investors were pooled and correlated with one another pro rata. When seeking out such commonality, the analysis looks at the relationship between the investors themselves to determine whether they were all facing similarly shared risks, collective action burdens and information asymmetries that could be mitigated by the presence of SEC regulation. 

But courts have also found other kinds of commonality sufficient to satisfy Howey’s common enterprise prong. Specifically, “vertical commonality” examines the relationship between investors and a promoter or issuer. Vertical commonality can exist even if investors receive diverging returns as among each other (in contrast to horizontal commonality). Some courts have divided vertical commonality into a “broad” and a “strict” variance. In the case of “broad vertical commonality,” investors need not show any kind of intertwined risk between themselves and a promoter as long as they are dependent on the promoter’s efforts with respect to money management (in other words the promoter gets paid regardless of whether investors make money). “Narrow vertical commonality,” on the other hand, requires showing shared risk between the investors and the promoter (that is, the promoter only gets paid if the investors make money).

The common enterprise components of the Howey test affect different securities-adjacent businesses in different ways. Consider cryptocurrencies in their various forms. For example, a crypto-token that is digitally developed by a promoter to raise money for a venture and sold to buyers with the promise of future returns from the business might look like a pretty conventional type of common enterprise. Money is pooled. And the fortunes of the purchasers are linked to each other and to the success of the promoter’s efforts. But relatively more “decentralized” cryptocurrencies like Bitcoin look quite different. There is no typical promoter as such. That said, purchasers of the crypto-token will see their fortunes rise and fall depending on whether the currency is adopted widely and appreciates in value. Because of this shared state, it may be argued that holders are part of a kind of common enterprise, but one that happens to be a uniquely decentralized one. Does that satisfy the definition of an investment contract? Or does the absence of pooling by a central issuer as well as its apparent absence for the purposes of vertical commonality mean that the definition of common enterprise is unable to reach relatively more decentralized cryptocurrencies? 

The definitions of an investment contract—and interpretations of the Howey test—provide one important example of how SEC enforcement through adjudication can make policy—and why incremental litigation against one sort of coin can still leave important questions unanswered with regard to other kinds of coins. But additional examples abound of critical policy derived by or generated through litigation. For example, it has been courts that have not only defined what counts as “material” information but have also defined its application for industry standards and practice. What a reasonable investor would find important given the “total mix” of information is both a fact based inquiry and court policymaking that, while based on the specific circumstances of litigants in a dispute, ultimately define the outer reaches of securities law and the agency’s jurisdiction. The meaning of materiality has thus been worked out through a number of enforcement actions, as well as through other adjudications. For example, the SEC has worried that ordinary investors will not understand the material risks posed by cryptocurrency investments.

In these instances, the line between “finding the law” and “creating the law” can become blurry as the law intersects with unanticipated, real-world operations of new technologies. Cryptocurrencies offer plenty of obvious examples: do staking services constitute an “investment of money,” where the customer maintains control and ownership of staked digital assets? Does it matter when those wishing to stake their crypto assets do so to protect the integrity and continuity of a blockchain rather than for the reward of additional tokens? Does the presence of a permissioned blockchain, in which participation in its infrastructure is restricted rather than open to all—necessarily mean that its native cryptocurrency is “dependent on the efforts of others”? Can an instrument that begins life as a security become so decentralized in its underlying governance that, eventually, it no longer qualifies as one? And if so, what constitutes the legal inflection point at which this transition occurs? Just as these questions involve the application of long-standing principles to new fact patterns, they can also involve exercising judgment about how entire domains of technology, and their supporting operational systems and transactions should be categorized, and under what circumstances. Thus, they represent issues that could well be clarified as a matter of administrative rulemaking or more informal guidance (for instance, through no-action letters). But at the same time, they could also constitute questions that are sufficiently substantive and related to precedent or statute that they end up being adjudicated in court.

II.  WHY WOULD AN AGENCY SEEK TO CREATE LAW THROUGH ENFORCEMENT?

Regulation by enforcement, while effective in times of crisis, is usually a choice, something regulators have themselves explicitly acknowledged. In this section, we review the discretion traditionally afforded to regulators, and the logic behind it. We then explore the criticisms and incentives faced by regulators who choose to engage in regulation by enforcement.

A.  Policymaking by Enforcement: The Historical Endorsement

So, why should agency leadership choose to make policy through adjudication rather relying on a more formal rulemaking process?

Regulators do not spend much time justifying their choice of policymaking tools. But courts have identified reasons why making policy on a case-by-case basis is useful. The traditional view, as we have observed, is that adjudication creates a common law regime where precedents produced by a series of enforcement actions can give regulated industry direction about the concerns of regulators, while giving regulators the flexibility to take a different approach in the next enforcement action.

The case most famously associated with this proposition is Chenery v. SEC. Chenery involved a breakup of a utility company holding company scheme that allowed insiders to control the utility despite having a tiny amount of equity in the enterprise by a pyramid corporate structure. The Supreme Court considered the case twice, and on the first occasion in 1943, invited the SEC to promulgate a rule setting forth limits on minority control through the holding company structure, something to which the dissent objected.

When the agency declined to do so, the Court, reviewing the case a second time in 1947, took the refusal in stride. It held that “the choice made between proceeding by general rule or by individual, ad hoc litigation is one that lies primarily in the informed discretion of the administrative agency.” As the Court observed,

Not every principle essential to the effective administration of a statute can or should be cast immediately into the mold of a general rule. Some principles must await their own development, while others must be adjusted to meet particular, unforeseeable situations. In performing its important functions in these respects, therefore, an administrative agency must be equipped to act either by general rule or by individual order. To insist upon one form of action to the exclusion of the other is to exalt form over necessity.

The idea is that administrative agencies should be able to engage in discrete, incremental lawmaking via litigation if this happens to be their preferred choice. Like common law, where judges are tasked with making rules on a case-by-case basis, adjudication allows courts and agencies to engage in problem-by-problem or issue-by-issue analysis, building on precedent to create a well-established body of law. For the Court, this sort of phased analysis may be appropriate when a rule may not obviously be the best approach or if the risks in implementation are unknown. This scenario may arise if there is a novel administrative scheme, or if the costs and benefits of a particular formal rule may not be clear. In such cases, regulators may decide to establish rules via courts as they recognize shortcomings, as opposed to putting forward an entire regulatory framework from the outset, or so the administrative law traditionalists have put it.

The limits to agency discretion, at least by this classical account, are few. Most important has been something akin to a regulatory “eye test”: as the First Circuit has put it, “an agency cannot merely flit serendipitously from case to case, like a bee buzzing from flower to flower, making up the rules as it goes along.” Especially when adjudications are made in-house, a showing of very different outcomes for similarly situated cases could form the basis for a conclusion by a court that the agency has been acting arbitrarily, and thus violating basic procedural norms and rules that authorize its work. Still, inaction by agencies—indeed a decision to pursue an enforcement action in one case, and not to do so in a similar case—is largely protected. As discussed below, the Supreme Court has held that an agency’s decision not to pursue an enforcement action is presumptively unreviewable, as such actions are “committed to agency discretion by law,” under § 701(a)(2) of the Administrative Procedure Act (“APA”), with very narrow exceptions, such as when an agency is totally abandoning its statutory responsibilities.

B.  The Contemporary World of Regulation by Enforcement—and its Critics

Fast forward eighty years, and the deployment of regulation by enforcement has grown in ways unanticipated by the Court in Chenery. Some government officials have explicitly, and proudly, identified their willingness to use litigation as a means of progressing novel legal theories to change the law, rather than merely addressing unexpected or unanticipated facts with which agencies have limited experience. Others have leveraged enforcement proceedings to make policy after abandoning a failed notice and comment processes. Yet others highlight an interest in sending strong signals to the market, seemingly prioritizing innocuous but “high profile” cases with media personalities to drive home their policy points and underscore their authority in contested fields. In doing so, commentators have argued that they depart from at least the tone and tactics taken on some other issues in similar circumstances in the past.

Not surprisingly, the flexibility to choose between making rules or making policy through a case-by-case adjudicatory process, has had its share of critics dating back to Chenery. In the last forty years, they have slowly earned greater prominence in both academic and regulatory circles. As early as 1982, Former SEC Commissioner Roberta Karmel argued that the SEC was using its enforcement powers to enlarge its regulatory turf, and suggested that rulemaking was better for predictability. A decade later, former SEC Chair Harvey Pitt and Karen Shapiro similarly concluded that regulation by enforcement was deployed to “utilize enforcement proceedings to develop new legal theories and remedies.” For Pitt and Shapiro, the enforcement paradigm, which emerged once the Supreme Court created a private right of action through doctrine rather than an explicit legislative rule, incentivized the agency to try to expand its regulatory powers through enforcement actions that sought to push at the existing edges of the doctrine. This created fertile ground for a consequential but otherwise fairly “amorphous” body of law, epitomized by the prohibition against insider trading, which has evolved in its application largely through litigation, rather than rulemaking.

The criticism has intensified recently, especially in the context of cryptocurrency, as well as climate-related and environmental-social-governance-related (“ESG”) rulemaking. Critics argue that the agency has made notable attempts to police what it has perceived as “green-washing” and illegal issuances of securities by cryptocurrency sponsors without first offering actionable or coherent rules on the implementation of standards for ESG principles or concrete guidelines to outline when a crypto-asset is a security. The criticisms, recently encapsulated by the Wall Street Journal, lament that the SEC’s “regulation by enforcement isn’t working and merely fuels market uncertainty.” For cryptocurrencies, SEC Commissioner Mark Uyeda has criticized his own agency for pursuing enforcement actions instead of making rules. “This is an example of a situation where regulation through enforcement does not yield the outcomes achievable through a process that involves public comment, because without the benefit of comments from crypto investors and other market participants, the commission is unable to consider their perspectives in developing an appropriate regulatory framework.” Another Republican SEC Commissioner, Hester Pierce, also complained that the agency has “tried to cobble together a regulatory framework through enforcement actions.” Not surprisingly, cryptocurrency entrepreneurs have also loudly criticized an approach driven by regulation by enforcement as regulatory technique.

The criticisms have bothered the SEC under the Biden administration. For example, the agency’s enforcement director has characterized the agency’s approach to emerging technologies and novel investment contracts as something that involves enforcement, but that is not using enforcement as a particular policymaking tool. As Director Gurbir Grewal noted in a keynote address, “this is not ‘regulation by enforcement.’ This is not ‘regulation by enforcement.’ This is not ‘regulation by enforcement.’ There. I have said it thrice and what I tell you three times is true.”

Notwithstanding such statements, accumulating critiques have set the stage over the years for considerable push-back striking at regulation by enforcement.. As, for example, the SEC diverted more cases to administrative adjudicatory proceedings, the securities bar responded with a successful effort to characterize these proceedings as technically unconstitutional based on the relative independence of agency adjudicators from political oversight. And even more recently, defendants have pushed to vacate civil monetary judgments based on the structure of regulatory agencies and “unprecedented agency action that ignores fundamental constitutional principles.” These tactics, grounded in separation of powers arguments, have found a receptive audience at the D.C. Circuit Court of Appeals, and ushered in a reduction in agency independence.

C.  A Continuum of Agency Incentives Driving Regulation by Enforcement

Many attempts to undermine regulation by enforcement are indirect and at times lead to outcomes eroding governmental supervision that are, in our view, inconsistent with the best interests of regulators and industry alike. Still, the rising tide of criticism is important insofar as it highlights an underappreciated theoretical and practical reality—namely, that there are a range of possible incentives that can drive the adoption of regulation by enforcement, or at least make it more attractive. Sometimes these incentives push agencies to enforce for the right reasons—regulators are unsure how to proceed, and so make policy on a case-by-case basis. By taking this careful approach, the damage of a bad choice is limited. In other cases, however, viewed more skeptically, regulators can use enforcement to avoid the burdens of other kinds of rulemaking—processes designed to make policymaking decisions better informed and more accountable.

We think that when regulators turn to adjudication, their incentives to do so can thus plausibly be characterized as lying along a continuum ranging from an interest in cautious case-by-case refinement and regulatory modulation to attempts to bypass administrative controls intended to enhance public participation and review. We have identified the bull case for regulation by enforcement as an essential gap filler and crisis response mechanism. For example, such an approach can reap gains where rulemaking still lags in its early stages or if its application and impact may be unclear. Regulation by enforcement can step in to tamp down on public harms in the absence of a clear rule or one that is under development. We have also explained that, as a matter of administrative law, courts have generally deferred to agency choices to prosecute, instead of legislating. But it is worth highlighting that there is a bare case, with tradeoffs that extend beyond the more usual concerns about whether regulation by enforcement makes for an unpredictable, unclear, and more ad hoc regulatory system.

First, agencies could pursue adjudications, or at a minimum find adjudication attractive, insofar as it enables rulemaking in ways that avoid the kind of public scrutiny and involvement entailed in administrative procedure. Normally, the rule writing process is just that—a process that, by definition, is intended to attract attention and inspection. The most visible and significant element of such review is the notice-and-comment process, designed to encourage commentary on rulemaking in ways that expose it to critique, criticism, and refinement. During notice-and-comment, new proposals are exposed to review by industry and civil society, and agencies are often required to, at a minimum, respond to the concerns raised in the review.

While this is how rulemaking is meant to work, the standard process can create political obstacles that draw negative media attention, private sector pushback, and can end up diluting or strengthening proposals in ways that might be out-of-sync with the views of agency leadership. The potential for such frictions provides one reason why adjudication can be such an attractive administrative tool. Adjudications limit the required responsiveness of agencies to the sort of wide-ranging assessments and suggestions that notice-and-comment rulemaking entails. Furthermore, they channel primary responsibility of dissent to the particular defendant selected by an agency to be the subject of an enforcement action. In this way, agencies can choose to set the terms of a debate, and even rope in other actors without necessarily giving them their day in court or a direct opportunity to participate. They can also potentially extract negotiated settlements from weaker or vulnerable actors without even ever having to go to court, and by publicizing the terms of the settlement and the infraction shape the public perception as to what the law “is.”

Practically, adjudication can also enable agencies to bypass some internal restraints accompanying administrative rulemaking. Following the decision of the DC Circuit in Business Roundtable vs. SEC, agency rulemaking must be supported, in most instances, by a detailed cost-benefit analysis in order for it to pass muster. The demand to produce such analyses in the promulgation of a rule means that agencies must demonstrate that their rule has been developed in a way that considers costs, if not numerically, then at least seriously. As the D.C. Circuit put it, “the Commission inconsistently and opportunistically framed the costs and benefits of the rule; failed adequately to quantify the certain costs or to explain why those costs could not be quantified,” it risks reversal for failing to follow its legal requirement that it consider efficiency, competition, and capital formation in its rulemakings. Often, this means employing experts (for example, economists) that can develop an unimpeachable economic case to support the rule. Otherwise, the rule might be challenged and struck down in court as one that is arbitrary and capricious. All the while, most of the records involved in the analysis are “FOIAable,” enabling any member of the public the right to access scrutinize them—and use them as the basis for potential criticism of agency leaders or even litigation. In particularly contentious, ideological or high-stakes areas of oversight, playing offense by litigating—as opposed to engaging in rulemaking and waiting to be sued—can present a lower risk route to making policy.

Additionally, adjudication need not be as rigorous as typical administrative processes. As Jim Cox has observed, “when the SEC brings enforcement actions, it does not have to do cost-benefit analysis.” Additionally, while litigation itself consists of a (potentially long and winding) process, it does immediately signal the policy posture of the agency without opening the agency up to the same kinds of risks entailed in rulemaking. The administrative checks of rulemaking, for better or worse, can be mostly avoided by pursuing an enforcement action.

Adjudication also enables agencies to shift responsibility for rulemaking to the courts, a shirking strategy. In short, regulatory agencies, especially when faced with politically difficult choices, may wish to punt the ultimate responsibility for crafting particular rules to other actors. To the extent that legislation is not forthcoming, agencies may view courts as more optimal forums for hashing out difficult questions in ways that relieve agencies of the pressure, or responsibility, associated with “making law” through the administrative process. As a part of this balancing process, agency administration may also be tempted to view an enforcement decision as a way to relieve relevant leaders of the need to confront the criticism involved in taking on contentious rulemaking. Generously, adjudication may arguably be seen as an expression of administrative modesty. More critically, it may be viewed as a kind of shirking or avoidance in cases in which regulators should really be coming forward to engage in detailed and ambitious rulemaking.

In other situations, agencies could alternatively turn to adjudication as an expressly political act. Litigation is, by definition, a confrontational exercise, whether in order to enforce existing rules or to make new policy. As a result, regulation by enforcement presents an opportunity for agencies to signify their interest in taking action in ways that conform with certain policy or ideological moorings. Litigation can be designed to bolster or echo the Executive’s priorities or the priorities of key members of Congress to demonstrate high performance and in the process, enhance the career prospects of agency leaders. Alternatively, agencies could perceive certain forms of conduct as especially odious or dubious, and as a result, wish to engage in litigation as a more effective route of bringing media attention to the issue than the rulemaking process.

Finally, regulation by enforcement, even in the case of unsuccessful or discredited lawsuits, offers a means to extend the regulatory perimeter in ways unavailable under more conventional administrative rulemaking. To fully understand this particular strategy, it is important to understand that enforcement actions, particularly when exercised in novel ways, can freeze activity in the sector targeted by an agency. For example, by asserting that a particular digital asset is a security, a lawsuit can cool or temper the production or trading of that and similar digital assets. One question raised by the SEC vs. Wahi litigation, for example, was whether the mere claim by the SEC that a token was a security might prompt platforms that offer trading to preemptively delist it and any others deemed similar to avoid any potential punishment for themselves. This kind of preemptive deterrence effect takes place the moment the litigation is filed and can remain in effect for as long as the litigation is arising. As a consequence, the act of litigation can have an injunctive impact on actors, regardless of its merits, but with potentially high upside for a regulator. If successful, the suit helps to establish precedent that cannot be undone by future agencies; if unsuccessful, the suit chills politically undesirable but legal activities in ways that can extend far beyond its regulatory perimeter.

III.  THE LEGALITY AND TRADEOFFS OF REGULATION BY ENFORCEMENT

The turn to arguably more ambitious and consequential forays into regulation by enforcement raises two key questions. First, does this trend violate the strict letter of the law? And second, even if regulatory action is legally justified, does it offer a more effective means of governance – in other words, do the trade-offs justify the move? These inquiries are not mutually exclusive. For example, to the extent that the first question may not yield a straight-forward answer, the greater or lesser benefits of pursuing regulation by enforcement might impact judicial (in)tolerance for its continued use within the administrative canon. To state things differently, even if the practice might be acceptable legally or is at least ambiguous in this regard, it might yet fall foul of norms that underlie a deeper administrative commitment to the rule of law, such that the continued reliance on regulation by enforcement warrants further scrutiny.

A.  The Legal Question: Does It Violate the Law?

As described earlier, it is now well-established that courts afford expansive latitude to agencies in determining how best to forward rulemaking. But while Chenery supports the proposition that agencies should be given discretion to pursue lawmaking through the judicial system, it is not without its complications. Perhaps the most important of these is the  APA. Outlined earlier, the APA governs the process by which federal agencies develop and issue regulations. A bedrock of administrative practice and good governance, the APA includes requirements for agencies to publish notices of proposed and final rulemaking as well as to offer the public opportunities to provide comment on notices of proposed rulemaking. In this way, the APA provides a systematic form of an “external” check on the processes and procedures that govern administrative agencies charged with carrying out the grunt work of implementing congressional statutes and that exercise extensive latitude to do so under Chenery.

Enacted in 1946, just months before the release of the Chenery decision, the APA explicitly directs agencies to engage in a particularized and defined process when developing and writing rules. The process is intended to (1) ensure that agencies keep the public informed of their organization, procedures, and rules, (2) provide for public participation in the rule-making process, (3) prescribe uniform internal, organizational standards for the conduct of formal rule making and adjudicatory proceedings, and (4) restate the law of judicial review. As Ed Rubin writes, the APA is far from perfect. Some scholars suggest that it goes too far in its strictures, while others advocate that it does not go far enough. What is clear, however, is that it imposes a range of internal organizational norms alongside external checks that were devised as a way to respond to the rapid expansion of the administrative state following the New Deal reforms of the 1930s. 

But what does the APA mean for regulation by enforcement? In particular, does it curtail the ability of agencies to govern through litigation? Chenery, as noted above, does allow agencies considerable discretion to engage in both rulemaking and adjudication. But what about in more murkier instances? Specifically, could an agency willfully circumvent the APA, and its public policy goals, by engaging in regulation by litigation rather than through detailed rulemaking?

At least at first glance, the APA should make little difference to an agency’s ability to engage in regulation by enforcement, even if this reflects a deliberate strategy to circumvent the act. That is, because the APA lacks an anti-evasion clause, it should allow agencies to pursue a workaround its provisions. Moreover, courts have tended to interpret their ability to intervene in enforcement-related issues as being highly constrained. In Heckler v. Chaney, perhaps the most cited example of this principle, inmates sought redress after had been sentenced to death by lethal injection. They petitioned the FDA to take enforcement action to prevent the use of a specific drug protocol in capital punishment cases, alleging that use of these drugs constituted a violation of the Federal Food, Drug, and Cosmetic Act (FDCA). The FDA refused to intervene. Seeking review under the APA, the inmates filed suit in District Court asking that the FDA be required to stop the use of the drugs. The Court of Appeals held that the FDA’s refusal to take enforcement action was both reviewable and an abuse of discretion and remanded the case with the directions that the FDA be required “to fulfill its statutory function.” When the case was finally appealed to the Supreme Court, Chief Justice Rehnquist held that an agency’s decision to refrain from taking enforcement action should be assumed to be insulated from judicial review under the APA. That is, the FDA’s determination to avoid intervening was perfectly legitimate.

Looking deeper, however, it is worth asking whether Heckler is the last and complete word on the question. Crucially, it is silent on the issue of whether an agency’s decision to proactively enforce—rather than to refrain from enforcing – constitutes a potential violation of the APA. Heckler speaks to an agency refusing to deploy its resources in a case—the implication being, that by dint of its inaction, it chooses to leave the existing parameters of the law unchanged. By contrast, the Court in Heckler does not address what happens when an agency decides to bring a case—that is, to use its power, authority, and resources to sanction a regulated entity in a bid to further a specific interpretation of the law. Stated differently, Heckler leaves open the question of what legal consequences follow under the APA when an agency takes steps to either “make law” or “find law” through an active deployment of its enforcement power. As detailed in this Article, agencies might decide to pursue enforcement for any number of reasons. Chenery provides considerable latitude allowing such a strategy. But, as noted above, agencies may opt for launching litigation over rulemaking for reasons that might reflect a more cynical motive to affirmatively avoid the requirements of the APA. What happens then? Heckler, arguably, does not provide an answer.

To be sure, there are serious difficulties involved in identifying that line between an agency’s decision to pursue sanctions as part of its expected exercise of enforcement authority, and one in which its choices lie in deliberately (or recklessly) skirting the APA’s administrative process. Perhaps the most obvious is the challenge of finding evidence that might point to this administrative intention. As any lawyer knows, the task of uncovering “proof” that points to a state-of-mind is notoriously difficult. First, agencies are complicated creatures, staffed by many people, and it is difficult to attribute a single intent to so many individuals. Second, it requires looking for incriminating materials like internal memos, emails, or evidence of conversations had between decision-makers that could suggest a nefarious motive, and obtaining discovery against an agency in an APA case is very difficult. Obtaining this kind of material is challenging in the best of times. But it is especially difficult when agencies decide to pursue adjudication. Notably, the APA affirmatively shields agencies from having to publish their own internal organizational processes and rulemaking for public consumption. That is, there is no need for an agency to subject its own in-house enforcement deliberations to notice-and-comment. This leaves agencies relatively unconstrained in their abilities to develop their own procedures and processes without having to first subject them to outside scrutiny. Without such affirmative disclosure about internal policies, those looking to understand why agencies might be acting as they do have to rely on costlier measures. Discovery within litigation offers one expensive pathway, if a court is willing to allow it. Or, when possible, observers could also try to gain informational access through Freedom of Information Act requests that might yield clues as to agency process—but which itself has notable constraints as to what information must be provided by government. As a result, understanding whether an agency’s enforcement decisions are being driven by a wish to deliberately avoid the APA is, ironically enough, a task made more difficult by the very application of the APA itself.

In short, the question as to whether regulation by enforcement is legal under the APA is not entirely settled, even as most of the foundational principles are. On the one hand, agencies clearly have wide latitude under Chenery. And according to Heckler, the decision to avoid enforcing is essentially unreviewable. However, Heckler is incomplete: it does not address the scenario in which agencies affirmatively choose to bring a case. Moreover, there is little in either Chenery or Heckler that addresses a much more foundational inquiry, namely whether the pursuit of enforcement to circumvent the APA deliberately or recklessly is permissible, especially when it is intended to establish novel legal arrangements or dictates normally reserved for the rulemaking function.

B.  Legal Scrutiny Beyond the APA

The APA is but one vector of risk for agencies dependent on regulation by enforcement for rulemaking. Even where the APA offers few restrictions on agency action, perceptions of agency abuse or mischievousness can create considerable perils for the administrative state. Some commentators and scholars have noted that regulation by enforcement may lead to Congressional oversight hearings and the politicization of agency action—whether in the form of traditional rulemaking or litigation. But we think the consequences may be far greater, and perceptions of overzealous regulation could, over time, catalyze court reactions that ultimately undermine the very authority of the agencies to pursue their missions. At a minimum, litigation efforts can backfire, creating unfavorable precedent for the particular regulatory action or claim in question. But far more ominously, agency overreach can become grounds for courts to rein in the larger administrative authority. To be sure, normatively, imposing checks and balances on agencies constitutes the preserve of the judiciary. However, an ambitious agency pushing novel rules and doctrine in ways found to be unfair, unvetted, or unaccountable can increase the risk to itself of attracting judicial ire, and ultimately undermining the scope of its authority and sphere of influence.

Risks are particularly acute given the recent arc of Supreme Court decisions and posture. One possible target lies in the Chevron doctrine, a Constitutional principle many scholars argue was designed to get the courts out of the policing of agency policymaking. The Supreme Court has formally agreed to review its constitutionality, with a decision likely to be delivered in summer 2024, placing in jeopardy a critical lever by which agencies have exercised their authority with relative legal confidence over the decades. The doctrine, named after “the most cited case in administrative law,” outlines the standard of review courts must exercise when reviewing agency actions. For the first step, the reviewing court must ask whether, after “employing traditional tools of statutory construction,” it is evident that “Congress has directly spoken to the precise question at issue.” If so, the statute is “unambiguous[],” and the agency must not differ from Congress’ clearly expressed command. If, however, the court decides that the statute empowering the agency action is ambiguous, it then moves to step two of the inquiry. That step requires the court to uphold the agency’s interpretation so long as it is “based on a permissible construction of the statute.”

The standard was popular in the courts for decades, but increasingly seems to have fallen out of favor at the Supreme Court. Although the Court has not expressly overruled the case, it has unanimously restricted certain aspects of agency deference for in-house adjudication, and has not deferred to an agency interpretation of its government statute in six years. The Court did not cite Chevron in a majority opinion during the 2021 term, and cited it only three times in 2020, raising the likelihood that the Justices may have soured on the idea that courts should defer to agencies in most matters of legal interpretation. No agency would wish for the end of deference. But the seeming diminishing of Chevron at the Supreme Court opens up questions about what kinds of agency conduct may have irritated the Court sufficiently into taking a much closer and critical look at agency behavior. Here, the pursuit of enforcement, if designed or interpreted to bypass administrative norms, could provide an easy target for fully unwinding judicial deference.

And Chevron is not the only source of legal scrutiny. Notably, the Court has recently emphasized that an agency, when it breaks new policymaking ground, must “be cognizant that longstanding policies may have engendered serious reliance interests that must be taken into account.” An agency that has used enforcement actions to expand its regulatory turf, or to try out novel legal theories, might be particularly vulnerable to a charge that it arbitrarily failed to consider the settled expectations of a regulated (or previously unregulated) industry. Reliance interests are not dispositive, but they must be part of an agency’s reasoned decision-making. As the Supreme Court has explained, an agency “may determine, in the particular context before it, that other interests and policy concerns outweigh any reliance interests,” but “that difficult decision [is] the agency’s job.” An agency that proceeds through litigation is going to find it difficult to establish that its enforcement action included some sort of attention to the reliance interests of the defendant in the action.

Another possible vector of risk involves the “major questions doctrine,” which holds that courts should not defer to agency statutory interpretations that concern questions of “vast economic or political significance.” In 2022, the Court indicated that it intended to take the major question doctrine seriously with a last-day-of-term effort to gather the few cases applying the doctrine into a coherent whole. In West Virginia v. EPA, a case concerning the EPA’s power to encourage power plants to shift away from coal, and toward gas, wind, and solar, the Court explained that “in certain extraordinary cases . . . something more than a merely plausible textual basis for the agency action is necessary” to permit a new agency to go forward. To do so, the “agency instead must point to clear congressional authorization for the power it claims.” So far, the major questions doctrine has only been deployed by the Supreme Court to reverse rules—which incentivizes agencies like the SEC to avoid rulemaking and make policy through enforcement. Nonetheless, to the extent that regulation by enforcement is turf expansive, there is some risk that the courts could get frustrated and sanction regulators who move beyond their usual remits, however they do so, including by enforcement. Indeed, in the Wahi litigation outlined above, when the SEC sought to sanction defendants engaged in insider trading, arguing that the tokens traded are securities—led to a tussle on the major questions doctrine in court. In the Wahi case, defendants argued that the determination of tokens as securities constituted a major question, one that the SEC should seek Congressional permission to answer. 

This set of concerns, then, leads to what is perhaps the most fundamental question: whether agencies even have constitutional basis on which to bring their claims. In other words, agencies face the risk that the legal basis for their very authority to legislate and enforce comes under challenge. This risk is not theoretical. Already the courts of appeals have invoked two rarely invoked constitutional provisions, the nondelegation doctrine and the appropriations power, to stop relatively novel exercises of agency power, in a sort of thermostatic constitutional response to policymaking perceived as overzealous.

The nondelegation doctrine prohibits Congress from delegating its legislative powers to other entities—including the President, administrative agencies or, perhaps most disapprovingly, private organizations. In J.W. Hampton v. United States, the Court ruled that Congress must give its delegates an “intelligible principle” on which to base their legislative-like regulatory actions; and that, if it did so, it could appropriately transfer some of its legislative responsibilities to someone else. The doctrine has not been used to strike down legislation since 1935, so it is a doctrine that has, as Cass Sunstein has put it, had “one good year, and 211 bad ones (and counting).” The Fifth Circuit turned to the doctrine nonetheless to reject an enforcement action brought administratively by the SEC. The appellate court objected to the absolute discretion, per Chenery and Heckler, the agency thought it enjoyed when it came to choosing its forum for enforcement actions. When Congress did not create a standard about when to bring an enforcement action, if “the intelligible principle standard means anything, it must mean that a total absence of guidance is impermissible under the Constitution,” the court concluded, meaning that the decision to bring the case administratively had been made without any congressional guidance. That in turn meant that the enforcement proceeding had to be dismissed.

In Community Financial Services Association of America Ltd. v. CFPB, trade associations sought to challenge how the Consumer Financial Protection Bureau is funded, arguing the agency’s financing model—where it receives its working budget from the Federal Reserve rather than via the Congressional appropriations process—was unconstitutional. The plaintiff trade associations made the argument that the CFPB’s Payday Lending Rule was invalid owing, amongst other things, to its unusual funding process. The Fifth Circuit agreed, opening the door for plaintiffs to now contest any number of rules and enforcement actions delivered by the CFPB. While this case relates specifically to the workings of the CFPB, its implications can arguably extend much farther.

When agencies pursue litigation in ways that depart cavalierly from Chenery, and in ostensible circumvention of more traditional notice-and-comment rulemaking, their actions, however well intentioned, risk judicial pushback and may prove to be fertile grounds for rollbacks of administrative power more broadly. Stated differently, regulation by enforcement, while largely permissible under Chenery, does not mean that it is always allowed, and miscalculations carry risks for not only discrete cases, but also for the very powers of the regulatory state.

C.  The Normative Question: (When) Are the Trade-Offs Worth It?

Recapping, we earlier described the bull case for regulation by enforcement. Regulation by enforcement, rather than rulemaking, enables important gap filling and incremental rule-giving. Regulators can reduce errors and respond to unforeseen situations and even emergencies when necessary. In pushing high-profile litigation, agencies can additionally send a powerful signal of their intent to police the marketplace. This can foil activities by reckless risk-takers that become fearful of punishment and being publicly shamed in the media. A litigation-focused strategy—being public and liable to deter widely—can also instill confidence in the agency’s competence and its commitment to the cause it has been created to forward.

But there are deeper normative risks—both to the quality of the rulemaking, as well as to the underlying legitimacy of the regulatory framework. As we discuss below, regardless of the ultimate legality of rulemaking via litigation, its deployment can have costs to the quality of resulting rules, as well as to its acceptance as legitimate and fair. Furthermore, by shifting rulemaking to courts rather than agencies, the approach invites judicial interpretations and interventions that can ultimately undermine, rather than expand, regulatory authority. In other words, the courts can reject an agency’s adjudicatory efforts, and leave regulators red-faced, equipped with a much lighter reserve of institutional power that the agency might have wanted.

1.  Informational Costs and Rulemaking Quality

Favoring ex post adversarial litigation over formal ex ante rulemaking creates the possibility of a much lower-quality, lesser-informed policy intervention. The content of the new law can end up being less sophisticated substantively and more thinly informed.

There are internal-to-the-agency advantages of rulemaking. The act of developing a new rule requires an agency to engage in extensive research, crafting, analysis, and careful drafting even before it is presented to the public for scrutiny. This rulemaking process is designed to generate a deep reserve of information, opinion and analysis that exposes new proposals to various forms of expertise and the exigencies of real-world application. It requires agencies to engage substantively with the industry they are seeking to regulate, understand the risks, model the various directions that implementation might take, calibrate the costs that firms will have to pay when seeking to comply with the rule, as well as calculate the overall aggregate effect of the rule on the market (for instance through cost-benefit analyses). Well before the rule takes shape, then, it must be developed through an internal process designed to collect information, make a case for its benefits, to substantiate this argument for a potential challenge in the courts, and then to draft a rule that can coherently reflect the most optimal statement of the agency’s concerns versus the costs involved in execution.

There are also outside-of-the-agency benefits to rulemaking. Rulemaking can prompt extensive dialogue between the public and agencies even before proposals reach the notice-and-comment stage, opening up pathways for information to flow between agencies and others well before any drafting begins. Envisioning future rulemaking (because it is mandated by a Congressional statute), members of the public often try to engage with agencies early in a bid to see their interests reflected in upcoming proposal drafts—ahead of when the proposal is ready for publication in the notice-and-comment period. Lobbying by certain interest groups offers the most visible example of such a practice, where industry or citizen representatives seek out opportunities to make their views heard at early stages of drafting. In her study of the Volcker Rule—a post-2008 Financial Crisis measure designed to restrict how freely banks could engage in risk-taking for their own account—Kimberly Krawiec examined 8000 comment letters received by the Financial Stability Oversight Council in the pre-proposal stage. In addition to industry input, her study observed a surprising degree of private-public interest, bolstered by organizations like Americans for Financial Reform or Public Citizen. To be sure, scholars diverge on whether such public commentary is, in fact, expert and informative for agencies. However, as Krawiec notes, the fact of receiving such input can often be informative in its own way, notwithstanding concerns about substantive content.

Litigation, by contrast, involves fewer informational inputs. In lieu of notice-and-comment, it offers informational opportunities through three critical tools: the discovery process, testimony, and amicus briefs. Discovery, for its part, creates the parameters for dispute and comprises the occasion where parties to the process supply information to one another. But discovery is an imperfect proxy for detailed policy-based research. It is centered on the case itself and, therefore, on the alleged conduct of the defendant. Its data gathering and analysis may not reach the interests of the industry as a whole, or offer a rigorous public analysis conducted by the agency about the merits of the case. And even where it is collected, not all data will be presentable during a dispute and could be disregarded for any number of legal or procedural reasons.

Amicus briefs or “friends of the court” briefs, by contrast, enable expert and interested third parties to offer instruction and insight to the court. However, like litigation, amicus briefs do not involve the opportunity for policy engagement, much less counterproposals. Instead, they represent occasions for authors to provide legal theory or partial legal analyses courts may or may not deem to be relevant to assigning liability or guilt. As a result, full scrutiny need not be brought to bear on specific rulemaking agenda items. And there is also no requirement or even expectation for agencies to respond to amicus briefs, unlike in the case of rulemaking, where regulators are expected to consider and address input gathered through the notice-and-comment process. For these reasons, even as the number of briefs issued has grown, scholars have long debated whether they really impact the decision-making of judges in practice. On the one hand, their contribution has been noted in cases where they offer judges specific expertise (for example, statistics) that is not included as part of the record. Briefs can be cited in decisions, showcasing their significance. On the other, judges are, as mentioned above, under no duty to heed such briefs. Unlike agencies that must be cognizant of the comments they receive and cannot just ignore them, judges can exercise far greater discretion. Indeed, one study points to a divergence in attitude to amicus briefs between judges. While some welcome the interventions, others like Judge Richard Posner have been openly hostile. Ultimately, the receptivity toward amicus briefs, even in their limited utility, can depend on a number of factors, such as the particular court in which they are filed, the judge in the case, the kind of brief offered (for example, offering specific expertise), as well as whether the person submitting is respected and trusted by the court.

Testimony, as a final source of information, comprises statements gathered by critical parties to the dispute. It can take place in the form of pre-trial depositions or in-court testimony. Like both discovery and amicus briefs, testimony is generally tied to specific facts. And in order to be admitted into deliberations, it, like discovery, must meet procedural and substantive requirements, like avoiding hearsay and other requirements—standards inapplicable to notice-and-comment. Moreover, larger questions deemed irrelevant to the dispute, even if critical or central to policy considerations, will have no sanctioned weight in the adjudication—even where agencies engage courts in order to regulate by enforcement.

2.  Fairness and Legitimacy

Regulation by enforcement, as opposed to regulation by administrative process, also raises important fairness and legitimacy concerns. The APA aims to create a system of procedural fairness around the rulemaking process to ensure that authorities govern through proper, transparent, well-evidenced, and objective processes. Through publicity, notice-and-comment, and mandatory agency engagement, those that may be bound by new legislation —as well as anyone else—is invited to provide input and contribution. Judicial review of rulemaking offers the ultimate check on the implementation of the process. Though agencies enjoy considerable deference, they do confront the possibility of being challenged, for example, where regulations are found to be arbitrary and capricious. Moreover, the process is intended to give regulated entities and the public a preview of the expectations and rules that will apply to them.

By pursuing an enforcement action as a first means of creating new law, policymakers raise the risk of doing so in a way that, justified or not, could appear to give those affected scant prior notice of illegality or expected punishment. Or even where parties ought to understand or expect enforcement, the absence of a rule can create unequal compliance opportunities for firms. Some firms will have greater resources to track potential regulatory actions. Moreover, certain defendants are better positioned to bear these costs than others. Smaller companies may have few resources to defend themselves, while larger actors might be better placed to withstand and contest the action. The Wahi case again offers an example. Rather than target large entities like crypto trading platforms or issuers, the SEC chose to bring a case against three individuals, whose capacity to direct vast resources to the litigation was arguably extremely limited. This asymmetry leads to the potential for procedural unfairness (or perceived unfairness) in situations where smaller defendants or individuals may be specifically selected as test cases, owing to the likelihood that they fail to contest the claim (because they are small firms) or, conversely, if they are sufficiently high profile that agencies can generate the needed buzz, publicity, and wider deterrent effects on smaller players in order to make the case for a new jurisprudence. Because rulemaking in such cases arises by dint of an adversarial process, it arguably necessitates an even greater need to show procedural fairness. As enforcement implies the need for defendants to fight back, it makes sense to consider whether those subject to new rules have the capacity, notice, and opportunity to take on the contest.

Finally, fairness norms may also call into relief the motives of agencies to make new rules and ultimately their authority and technocratic credibility. As Kevin Stack observes, achieving coherence within the law represents an essential value within the regulatory system. Agencies, he notes, have a key role in implementing coherence to facilitate the creation of a legal “system” that aims to be internally and philosophically consistent. They are expected to deliberate and execute policy in a way that can connect into and reflect the wider administrative/legal system of which it is a part, to offer continuity with past practice as well as contemporary policy priorities.

When policy is generated through litigation that does not derive from clearly articulated rulemaking, or that is designed to shape industries or punish particular actors without prior notice and guidelines, there may be doubts about the agency’s adherence to these rule of law norms. For example, in August 2023, the Court of Appeals for the D.C. Circuit ruled against the SEC in the agency’s decision to deny asset manager Grayscale’s application for a bitcoin exchange-traded fund. Strikingly, in reviewing the legality of the SEC’s decision, the D.C. Circuit unanimously determined that the agency had acted in an “arbitrary and capricious manner” when it refused Grayscale’s petition. In other words, there emerges, in short, a difference between “filling a gap” and “filling a legislative void.” The former involves targeted elaboration of existing legislative or administrative processes and thinking. The latter attempts to create a legal artifice in the absence of such groundwork. Eliding the rigors of information gathering and public input can, in short, have costs. Rather than being perceived as fair, impartial, and guided by their public interest mission, deficiencies within the rulemaking process can fuel negative views of agencies as being excessively political, insufficiently motivated by internal expertise and lacking technocratic professionalism. Ultimately an erosion of trust in the fundamental norms governing agency rulemaking can curtail confidence in the mission of the agency and its ability to execute it successfully and legitimately.

III.  WHEN SHOULD AGENCIES REGULATE BY ENFORCEMENT?

Enforcement is a critical function of the regulatory state, and for the most part noncontroversial. Government agencies are charged with mission-critical responsibilities aimed at serving the public and undertaking actions that preserve the integrity of rules designed to protect investors, consumers, and even the overall economy. For what purpose enforcement is used can, however, vary. At times, agencies may seek to utilize their enforcement powers in ways that preserve the integrity of existing law; at others, they may seek to establish new legal theories, or even regulatory regimes, powers, or jurisdiction. In all cases, discrete and expansive, regulatory action may be considered essential, or even vital and a necessary action to send powerful signals to the market in a timely manner. Or it could deliberately enable what are ultimately abusive practices by agencies.

The sheer variety of ways and motives driving regulation by enforcement raises a number of pressing doctrinal questions. Overall, regulation by enforcement is a firmly established and jurisprudentially sanctioned practice. Still, precedent has not to our knowledge distinguished among the different scenarios in which it is practiced. This void offers the courts, and especially a Supreme Court skeptical of broad remits of administrative authority, considerable leeway to respond in ways that regulators may find surprising. Agencies also risk the possibility that their actions could have serious reputational consequences, and provide fodder for legislative actions clipping their budgets, and legal decisions eroding their very authority.

Enforcement by regulation should thus be undertaken with a clear understanding by regulators as to its risks and exercised in ways that optimize the long-term interests of agencies, their stakeholders, and regulated entities. From this standpoint, we foresee a number of helpful rules of thumb. Ultimately, some of the same kinds of cost-benefit and data analysis compelled in rulemaking should be institutionally embedded in agencies for enforcement actions. Here, coordination among enforcement and rulemaking staff might be helpful. We understand that the distinction between preserving and creating law can be murky, but cases in which serious questions arise, the cost benefit analysis should, in turn, likewise increase in its rigor. A practical understanding of the divergent incentives of staff in each office is warranted, as well as the incentives of agency stakeholders in approving and guiding enforcement actions.

Additionally, enforcement actions in novel policy areas should be ideally initiated as early as possible in the lifecycle of the disputed market practice as to mitigate subsequent market disruption. If an entity is selling what an agency believes is an unregistered security, or if an entity is violating rules as an unregistered securities exchange or unlicensed bank, enforcement activity should be brought to bear early—or a rulemaking initiated. Waiting years to bring an enforcement action can be misinterpreted, as well as heightens perceptions of agencies acting only when convenient, politically palatable, or for other than merits-based reasons.

At the same time, regulation by enforcement is likely to be most accepted as legitimate when it is understood to be a last, rather than first resort. The APA is designed to enable not only democratic participation and accountability, but also predictability. Taking the pains to articulate the agency’s expectations, even if only through soft law tools like staff guidance and no action letters, are more likely to set the stage for more broadly accepted enforcement actions with high policy throughput. Yet even here, in order to be effective, the guidance should be coherent, thought through, and offer a clear set of expectations for market and industry participants built on top of established legal principles, precedent, and rulemaking.

Finally, enforcement actions designed to promote policy should embrace some of the public facing norms of administrative process. Adjudications are, as mentioned, by their very nature confrontational, and usually represent a zero-sum game for participants. Nevertheless, regulatory agencies should, when possible, respond to amicus briefs and other interventions by industry and civil society, even in the context of legal proceedings. By conferring voice to a broader set of stakeholders, agencies can relieve the pressure generated by opting out of administrative process.

Ultimately the increasing attention directed toward regulation by enforcement creates a rich research area for academics, policymakers, and the press. Commentators would do well to keep an eye out for developments that suggest such strategies risk decisions that not only create bad precedent, but also risk decaying the very authority of the agency.

At the same time, the drivers behind regulation by enforcement deserve greater scholarly and popular attention. To some extent, the turn to enforcement can be attributed to partisan politics. Litigation can further the political objectives of democratically elected representatives who have appointed personnel to the administrative state. And it can be used to bolster the bona fides of officials and regulators seeking greater visibility, and perhaps, professional promotion. And in such cases, the incentives of a regulator may not necessarily conform with their agency, with the regulator having moved on when the agency faces potentially adverse litigation or judicial weakening. Still, regulation by enforcement may also reflect how changes in the reception of administration of policy may drive the exploration of a greater toolbox for regulators. In this sense, litigation may beget litigation, and proliferating lawsuits by private actors to agency rulemaking incents regulators to sue preemptively instead, creating a doom loop of legal challenges that not only stifle courts, but also ultimately add to regulatory uncertainty.

In the end, identifying and disentangling motives will not always be easy. Though attempts to do so will continue to abound—if not by courts, then from legislators and the public. In this process, the credibility of all actors will be tested. The ability of government to solve problems resides in trust, just as does the ability of the private actors to sell their goods and services. The outcry from “regulation by enforcement,” however well or ill-informed, at a minimum indicates that the trust is no longer always there. The key for regulators, lawmakers, and courts will be to see just what is responsible for its decay, and how to restore it in ways that advance the public interest.

96 S. Cal. L. Rev. 1297

Download

* Chris Brummer is the Agnes Williams Sesquicentennial Professor of Financial Technology at Georgetown University Law Center.

† Yesha Yadav is the Milton R. Underwood Chair, Associate Dean and Professor of Law at Vanderbilt Law School.

‡ David Zaring is Elizabeth F. Putzel Professor of Legal Studies at the Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania. For their invaluable insights, perspectives and comments, we are most grateful to Anita Bandy, Anupam Chander, Patrick Corrigan, Elizabeth de Fontenay, Keir Gumbs, Kathryn Judge, Don Langevoort, Jai Massari, Donna Nagy, Peter Molk, Alex Platt, Todd Phillips, Adam Pritchard, Elizabeth Pollman, Bob Rasmussen, Adriana Robertson, Kevin Stack, Bob Thompson, Anne Tucker, Yuliya Guseva, and to participants at the BYU Winter Deals Conference, the Digital Transformation in Business and Law Symposium sponsored by the Southern California Law Review at USC and the University of Pennsylvania Institute for Law and Economics (ILE) Roundtable (Spring 2023). We thank Alex Ang Gao for excellent research assistance. Errors are our own.

Divided Agencies

Clashes between presidential appointees and civil servants are front-page news. Whether styled as a “deep state” hostile to its democratically selected political principals or as bold “resisters” countering those principals’ ultra vires proposals, accounts of civil servant opposition are legion. Move beyond headlines, however, and little is known about the impact of political divisions within agencies on their workaday functioning.

This Article presents the first comprehensive, empirical examination of the effects of intra-agency political dynamics on policymaking. Leveraging data on political preferences based on campaign donations, we identify “ideological scores” for both appointees and civil servants in dozens of agencies over thirty-four years—the first measure of the political gap between these two groups across agencies and time. We use these scores to examine how ideological divergence between appointees and civil servants affects regulatory activity.

We find that agencies with greater distance between these two groups—which we term “divided agencies”—may adopt a more cautious posture. They tend to extend the rulemaking process and allow consideration of late-filed comments. These features provide appointees with extra time to gather and digest comments from politically aligned outside experts. Divided agencies’ caution may extend to the completion of final rules, which—in some but not all models—tend to be less numerous. Remarkably, we find no evidence that divided agencies are any less successful in shepherding proposed rules to final status. That finding casts doubt on the claim that the longer rulemaking timeframes in these agencies are attributable to civil servants’ attempts to derail oppositional appointees’ initiatives. Instead, one possible interpretation is that divided agencies’ caution pays off.

These findings imply that, with agency heads oscillating between left and right based on the party in power, the generally more moderate civil service can serve as a ballast. Specifically, faced with appointees that may be responsive only to a bare electoral majority, the presence of oppositional civil servants may encourage regulatory caution and push decision-making away from the extremes—thus, paradoxically, moving policy toward the median voter.

Our findings also spotlight the critical role that the notice-and-comment process—which is often maligned as pretextual—can play in divided agencies. Generalist appointees face a principal-agent problem when crafting rules: their key source of necessary in-house expertise, civil servants, may be misaligned. In this circumstance, comments from outside allies can provide a check on civil servants’ work. That civil servants can play a promajoritarian, moderating role in divided agencies highlights the importance of preserving civil service protections—especially in today’s polarized political climate.

Introduction

Secretary of the Interior Ryan Zinke, who served during the Trump Administration, and John Morton, who helmed Immigration and Customs Enforcement (“ICE”) under President Obama, may not have much in common politically, but they do share one experience: they managed agencies in which approximately one-third of their workforce was estranged. A proponent of increasing industry access to public lands, Secretary Zinke believed he had “thirty [percent] of the crew that’s not loyal to the flag” concerning that goal.[1] He compared his situation to capturing “a prized ship at sea and only the captain”—that would be Secretary Zinke, incidentally, a former Navy SEAL—“and the first mate row over” to manage the captured crew.[2] In response, some Interior Department civil servants styled themselves “the disloyals,” printing T-shirts with that epithet.[3]

Director Morton faced a similar mutiny. After issuing a directive prioritizing deportations of people convicted of crimes and urging prosecutorial discretion in other cases,[4] the union representing nearly thirty-nine percent of ICE employees passed a no-confidence vote against Morton’s leadership.[5] That move was unprecedented.[6]

That other apostates can be found across the executive branch is unsurprising;[7] the conditions are ripe for such conflicts. Civil servants often hold differing views from appointees.[8] With only four thousand appointees atop a federal workforce of over two million[9]—many of whom hold job protections—the former group’s ability to supervise the latter will, by practical necessity, be incomplete. As political polarization grows and hardball tactics typically associated with electoral politics enter administrative agencies,[10] we expect that conflicts between appointees and civil servants will only increase.

In recent years, legal scholars have turned their attention to examining these inner workings of administrative agencies. For instance, some scholars posit that competing centers of power within agencies—civil servants and appointees, along with public participants—serve a checking function on each other’s power and thus mimic the more familiar constitutional separation of powers.[11] Others theorize about the policies produced by agencies that contain competing powers, some of which pull in majoritarian and others in countermajoritarian directions.[12]

Yet while the legislative consequences of political divisions among the branches of government are well studied,[13] relatively little empirical work analyzes the impact on policy of political divisions within agencies.[14] Empirically, political dynamics inside administrative agencies remain terra incognita in some important respects. How do agencies in which key subgroups are at loggerheads differ from agencies that are more politically cohesive? Do deeply divided agencies take longer to regulate, perhaps because of distrust or civil servant foot-dragging? Is White House review more exacting for these agencies, on the theory that White House officials are less likely to trust proposed rules emanating from ideologically divided entities? And do these agencies ultimately produce fewer rules?

This Article seeks answers to these questions. It examines how ideological differences between political appointees and civil servants affect the rulemaking process. These two groups share power within agencies, with generalist appointees relying on expert civil servants to implement the former group’s preferred policies. That division gives rise to a well-studied principal-agent problem: appointees must rely on civil servants who may have very different policy preferences and over whom appointees have limited ability to monitor or control.[15]

Faced with agents they may distrust, appointees may seek out and spend more time considering informed “second opinions” from other sources. These alternative sources of information include comments received during the notice-and-comment process, informal feedback from allies in Congress, and recommendations from advisory committees of outside experts occupying a privileged position within agencies. Indeed, public choice theorists posit that administrative structures and processes can serve just this purpose.[16]

We put this theory to the test, examining how appointees respond when their agents in the civil service hold differing views. To do so, we first develop a measure of ideological distance over time and within agencies so that we can identify divided agencies.

Existing measures are inadequate for that purpose,[17] so we create our own. We leverage a dataset on ideological preferences based on campaign donations to do so. We use these data to generate dynamic “ideal point” estimates for agency heads and civil servants in forty-seven agencies over thirty-four years—and thus, a new measure of the ideological gap between these two groups across agencies and time.[18] We then connect this measure to data concerning the rulemaking process.

Our results show that divided agencies—that is, those with ideologically opposed agency heads and civil servants—adopt a slower rulemaking posture than agencies that are more unified. Several of our findings suggest that greater caution may be at play. Once civil servants generate a proposed rule, appointees take their time. While we cannot rule out all alternative explanations, we observe that one feature of the delay is consideration of late-filed comments. Considering late-filed comments allows appointees to hear from a greater number of ideologically aligned outside groups as a check on civil servants’ work. Delay may also result from appointees spending additional time assessing those comments. In either case, slower rulemaking at divided agencies suggests that appointees may be utilizing rulemaking procedures to blunt civil servants’ informational advantages. Additionally, divided agencies may tend to issue fewer rules. That their rules are no less likely to become final, however, is perhaps evidence that their caution pays off.

This claimed cautious approach means that, whatever policy changes one desires in a first-best world, the reality of policymaking in divided agencies likely will leave one disappointed. Indeed, divided agencies are likely status quo-preserving. Whether this feature is normatively desirable turns, in part, on one’s risk aversion and the extent to which one values policy certainty.

Given that partisan polarization—and thus divided agencies—likely will persist into the foreseeable future, our findings provide a set of best practices for agencies to function as well as possible under these conditions. The policy implication that most closely follows from our findings is that officials must preserve the independence of the civil service. At a time when that independence is challenged, our findings about rulemaking suggest that civil servants comprise a moderating counterweight against more ideologically extreme appointees; thus, they serve as a bulwark against wild changes in regulatory policy. With agency leadership swinging between liberal and conservative poles, as we find, civil servants—who tend to be more moderate, albeit left of center—can pull agency policies toward the median voter. This moderation serves to improve democratic representation in agency policymaking: appointees are aligned with the Presidents who appoint them, and Presidents tend to be more ideologically extreme than the median voter. Allowing policy to swing all the way to their appointees’ preferences would therefore not reflect the public’s preferences. In contrast to common laments of employment-protected civil servants serving as a countermajoritarian force in policymaking, we show that they can serve a democratizing function in divided agencies.[19]

Further, to prevent divided agencies from descending into the gridlock and paralysis that plague other polarized institutions, appointees must have access to high-quality information from ideological allies, which we infer from divided agencies’ greater willingness to consider late-filed comments. We argue that the notice-and-comment process is well suited to transferring high-quality information to distrustful appointees. Notice-and-comment also may discourage civil servants, aware that their work will be “checked” by outsiders, from straying too far from their principals’ goals. Additional measures to inject diverse outside sources of information into agency decision-making could further enhance agencies’ ability to function, even in a challenging partisan climate within their walls—though they would increase resource costs associated with rulemaking.

This Article proceeds in four parts. Part I situates our study in twin literatures: empirical scholarship examining extra-agency influences on regulatory dynamics and descriptive and positive work concerning intra-agency dynamics. Part II presents our theory and expectations concerning the effects of appointee-civil servant preference divergence on regulatory processes and outputs. In Part III, we describe our research design, including our creation of an original dataset identifying appointees’ and civil servants’ political ideologies across agencies and time, and we present our analysis. Part IV discusses normative implications and offers policy prescriptions.

          [1].      Evan Osnos, Trump vs. the “Deep State, New Yorker (May 14, 2018), https://
http://www.newyorker.com/magazine/2018/05/21/trump-vs-the-deep-state [https://perma.cc/9862-ZBGM].

          [2].      Matthew Daly, Interior Chief’s Loyalty Comments Draw Widespread Criticism, Associated Press (Sept. 26, 2017), https://apnews.com/article/8c3ae77664f44159823903b3add31e65 [https://
perma.cc/AN4H-W8N6].

          [3].      Osnos, supra note 1.

          [4].      Memorandum from John Morton, Dir., U.S. Immigr. & Customs Enf’t, to All Field Off. Dirs., All Special Agents in Charge, & All Chief Couns., U.S. Immigr. & Customs Enf’t (June 17, 2011), https://
http://www.ice.gov/doclib/foia/prosecutorial-discretion/certain-victims-witnesses-plaintiffs.pdf [https://perma.
cc/JM2G-ZSVX].

          [5].      Ted Hesson, 7 Numbers that Tell the Story of an Immigration Boss’s Tenure, ABC News (June 17, 2013, 12:34 PM), https://abcnews.go.com/ABC_Univision/Politics/ice-director-john-mortons-
tenure-numbers/story?id=19422159 [https://perma.cc/W37D-R4QM]; see also Julia Preston, Single-Minded Mission to Block an Immigration Bill, N.Y. Times (June 1, 2013), https://www.nytimes
.com/2013/06/02/us/for-chris-crane-a-quest-to-block-an-immigration-bill.html [https://perma.cc/2ZLK-
TXUC] (providing figures used to calculate the union’s share of ICE’s workforce).

          [6].      Preston, supra note 5.

          [7].      See Osnos, supra note 1 (providing other examples).

          [8].      See infra Part III.

          [9].      Fiona Hill, Public Service and the Federal Government, Brookings (May 27, 2020), https://
http://www.brookings.edu/policy2020/votervital/public-service-and-the-federal-government [https://perma.cc/
JRK2-QYRM] (reporting the size of the federal nonmilitary, nonpostal workforce and the approximate number of political appointees).

        [10].      See Brian D. Feinstein & M. Todd Henderson, Congress’s Commissioners: Former Hill Staffers at the S.E.C. and Other Independent Regulatory Commissions, 38 Yale J. on Regul. 175, 223, 226 (2021) (documenting these developments).

        [11].      See Jon D. Michaels, Of Constitutional Custodians and Regulatory Rivals: An Account of the Old and New Separation of Powers, 91 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 227, 238–39 (2016); Gillian E. Metzger, The Interdependent Relationship Between Internal and External Separation of Powers, 59 Emory L.J. 423, 425 (2009); Neal Kumar Katyal, Internal Separation of Powers: Checking Today’s Most Dangerous Branch from Within, 115 Yale L.J. 2314, 2346 (2006).

        [12].      See Matthew C. Stephenson, Optimal Political Control of the Bureaucracy, 107 Mich. L. Rev. 53, 72 (2008).

        [13].      See generally Daryl J. Levinson & Richard H. Pildes, Separation of Parties, Not Powers, 119 Harv. L. Rev. 2311 (2006); Gary W. Cox & Mathew D. McCubbins, Setting the Agenda: Responsible Party Government in the U.S. House of Representatives (2005); John J. Coleman, Unified Government, Divided Government, and Party Responsiveness, 93 Am. Pol. Sci. Rev. 821 (1999); David R. Mayhew, Divided We Govern: Party Control, Lawmaking, and Investigations, 1946–2002 (2d ed. 2005).

        [14].      But see generally Rachel Augustine Potter, Bending the Rules: Procedural Politicking in the Bureaucracy (2019); Rachel Augustine Potter, Slow-Rolling, Fast-Tracking, and the Pace of Bureaucratic Decisions in Rulemaking, 79 J. Pol. 841 (2017) [hereinafter Potter, Slow-Rolling, Fast-Tracking]; Anne Joseph O’Connell, Political Cycles of Rulemaking: An Empirical Portrait of the Modern Administrative State, 94 Va. L. Rev. 889 (2008); George A. Krause, A Two-Way Street: The Institutional Dynamics of the Modern Administrative State (1999).

        [15].      See Mathew D. McCubbins, Roger G. Noll & Barry R. Weingast, Administrative Procedures as Instruments of Political Control, 3 J.L. Econ. & Org. 243, 243–44 (1987) (outlining this principal-agent problem).

        [16].      See, e.g., id. at 255 (“[P]olitical principals in both branches of government suffer an informational disadvantage with respect to the bureaucracy. . . . [M]any of the provisions of the Administrative Procedures [sic] Act solve this asymmetric information problem.”).

        [17].      For instance, measures based solely on the ideology of the appointing President fail to capture ideological differences in consecutive agency heads appointed by the same President. In other words, they do not capture enough variation over time. Other measures only occur sporadically in time.

        [18].      The included executive agencies are the Departments of Agriculture, Commerce, Defense, Education, Energy, Health and Human Services, Homeland Security, Housing and Urban Development, Interior, Justice, Labor, State, Transportation, Treasury, and Veterans Affairs (operating as the Veterans Administration until 1989); Environmental Protection Agency; and Small Business Administration. The included independent agencies are the Agency for International Development, Civil Aeronautics Board (until its dissolution in 1985), Commodity Futures Trading Commission, Equal Employment Opportunity Commission, Farm Credit Administration, Federal Communications Commission, Federal Deposit Insurance Corporation, Federal Emergency Management Agency (until its subordination to the Department of Homeland Security in 2003), Federal Energy Regulatory Commission, Federal Housing Finance Agency, Federal Housing Finance Board (until its dissolution in 2009), Federal Labor Relations Authority, Federal Maritime Commission, Federal Reserve Board, Federal Trade Commission, General Services Administration, Interstate Commerce Commission (until its dissolution in 1996), National Aeronautics and Space Administration, National Archives and Records Administration, National Credit Union Administration, National Transportation Safety Board, Nuclear Regulatory Commission, Office of Federal Housing Enterprise Oversight (until its dissolution in 2009), Office of Personnel Management, Pension Benefit Guaranty Corporation, Securities and Exchange Commission, Social Security Administration, Surface Transportation Board, and U.S. Postal Service. Also, the Internal Revenue Service, although part of the Treasury Department, is included as a separate agency.

        [19].      See Stephenson, supra note 12, at 72 (presenting a positive theory of this dynamic).

           *      Assistant Professor of Legal Studies and Business Ethics, the Wharton School of the University of Pennsylvania.

           †      Professor of Law, Political Science and Public Policy, University of Southern California Gould School of Law. We thank Adam Bonica, Devin Judge-Lord, and Rachel Potter for data, and Ming Hsu Chen, John Harrison, Erin Hartman, Kathryn Kovacs, Jeff Lubbers, Neysun Mahboubi, Jennifer Mascott, John McGinnis, Jon Michaels, David Noll, Anne Joseph O’Connell, Richard Pierce, Zach Price, Michael Rappaport, Noah Rosenblum, Amy Semet, Bijal Shah, Kevin Stack, Matthew Stephenson, Chris Walker, Dan Walters, Adam White, and participants at the Presidential Administration in a Polarized Era conference at the C. Boyden Gray Center for the Study of the Administrative State for helpful comments. The authors also gratefully acknowledge the Gray Center’s financial support of this research. 

  Download

Divided Agencies

Clashes between presidential appointees and civil servants are front-page news. Whether styled as a “deep state” hostile to its democratically selected political principals or as bold “resisters” countering those principals’ ultra vires proposals, accounts of civil servant opposition are legion. Move beyond headlines, however, and little is known about the impact of political divisions within

Read More »

The Social Context of the Law: A Critical Analysis of Reliance Interests in the Department of Homeland Security v. Regents of the University of California

In 2020, the U.S. Supreme Court ruled on the Department of Homeland Security v. Regents of the University of California case. The case concerned the rescission of the Deferred Action for Childhood Arrivals (“DACA”) policy, an issue that sparked the interest of a wide range of amicus curiae, including those in support of the policy. Using

Read More »

Dimensional Disparate Treatment

The Supreme Court’s decision in Bostock v. Clayton County was an important victory for gay and transgender workers—but the Court’s textual analysis has failed to persuade a number of thoughtful commentators, and it threatens to leave anti-discrimination law in disarray. The root of the problem is that Bostock trumpeted a “simple test” of but-for causation

Read More »

A Closer Look at the PTAB Operation

Prior to the passage of the America Invents Act (“AIA”) in 2011,[1] allegedly low-quality patents were allowed to proliferate. Many of these low-quality patents contributed little to innovation because holders of these patents did not practice the technologies they had exclusive rights over. Rather, these patent holders used the patents to challenge actually productive patents owned by operating companies. Unfortunately, there are only two ways to challenge such low-quality patents: through federal court litigation or administrative patent opposition mechanisms.

In light of these problems, Congress passed the AIA and empowered the United States Patent Trademark Office (“USPTO”) to reevaluate and revoke previously issued patents through the creation of the Patent Trial and Appeal Board (“PTAB”).[2] The goal of these post-grant administrative proceedings is to serve as an efficient alternative to district court litigation and to lower the cost of invalidating low-value patents.[3] Despite Congress’s best intentions, there is still much uncertainty regarding these cancellation procedures. Contrary to congressional expectations, the U.S. patent system ranking dropped consecutively from first to tenth to thirteenth in its patent protection ranking between 2017 and 2018, receiving the lowest score in patent opposition out of all developed countries’ post-grant opposition mechanisms.[4] Such downward trend raises the question: Are these subpar ratings merely a result of the new tribunal’s growing pains which will soon subside, or do they indicate a systemic flaw of the U.S. patent opposition system?

Out of the new PTAB’s proceedings, inter partes review (“IPR”), a process by which the PTAB reconsiders or cancels previously issued patents, has been exceedingly popular for patent challengers. This Note analyzes over 11,000 PTAB proceedings across different industries and technologies, and attempts to evaluate the PTAB’s run over its eight-year life in order to provide an empirical perspective on whether the PTAB has gone too far invalidating patents.

This Note will inform the debate over how well the PTAB is working by looking at: (1) its treatment of Non-practicing Entities (“NPEs”) and Patent Assertion Entities (“PAEs”); (2) serial IPR petitions; and (3) concurrent litigation. All three areas will be analyzed across different industries using original empirical data. The data will show that while Congress has mostly achieved its intended goals of making patent opposition litigation faster and cheaper at the PTAB, there are unintended consequences of the PTAB mechanisms.

As I will describe in greater detail below, the specific findings are the following:

       First, the PTAB has largely succeeded in providing an additional avenue to raise invalidity challenges against NPEs and PAEs, especially in the information technology (“IT”) sector. However, there has also been an alarming rise in invalidity petitions aimed at actual operational companies, a trend across industries but especially in the biosciences. Among PTAB invalidity proceedings against NPEs/PAEs, 52% of them are against patents related to the IT industry whereas only 6% are against patents in life science;

Second, among 11,909 PTAB petitions filed, there are 7,074 unique patents addressed. In other words, 41% of the time the PTAB looks at a petition, the Board had already seen the same patent challenged some other way in another petition. On a per-patent basis, 32% of the patents have been challenged more than once. Such serial petition problems also exist across industries. The problem is the most prevalent within the IT industry. In fact, 36% of the patents addressing software technologies are challenged more than once, whereas 30% of the patents addressing biosciences are challenged more than once;

Third, the PTAB mechanisms are used in unintended ways by certain entities.[5] For example, almost one in five patents in front of the PTAB, 19% to be precise, faces multiple invalidation petitions brought by the same challengers.

Fourth, while the institution rate is decreasing across industries, petitions against software patents are instituted at the highest rate of 75%, whereas petitions against bioscience patents are instituted at the rate of 68%;

Fifth, the heightened concerns on the invalidity rate of PTAB petitions (most commentators report a rate of around 80%) could be misleading because the overall rate of petitions being held partially or entirely invalid out of all petitions filed is only 22%. The 80% invalidity rate is calculated by dividing petitions that are held partially or entirely invalid by petitions that received final written decision; however, the majority of petitions filed do not ever receive a final written decision;

Last, patent challengers who resort to invalidating patents at the PTAB are highly likely to have parallel lawsuits against the same patents, as 83% of the PTAB petitions have a co-pending district court case.

In Part I, I will introduce the U.S. patent system, the history and purpose of the AIA, and the PTAB. I will discuss the popularity of one specific PTAB proceeding IPR and present both sides of the debate around IPRs, the USPTO director’s discretion, and the Supreme Court’s scrutiny over the PTAB in recent years. In Part II, I will describe the study design, which includes its data source and data structure. In Part III, I will expand upon the findings and review how the PTAB operations have changed under different directors. At the end, I will conclude my analysis.

 

 

          [1].      35 U.S.C. §§ 311–319. In September 2012, petitions for inter partes review first became available. Id.

          [2].      See id. § 6(b).

          [3].      H.R. Rep. No. 112-98, pt. 1, at 39–40, 48 (2011), as reprinted in 2011 U.S.C.C.A.N. 67, 69, 78 (discussing that post grant reviews were intended to be “quick and cost effective alternatives to litigation”).

          [4].      See U.S. Chamber of Com., Glob. Innovation Pol’y Ctr., U.S. Chamber International IP Index 7–9 (6th ed. 2018), http://globalipcenter.wpengine.com/wp-content/uploads/
2018/02/GIPC_IP_Index_2018.pdf [https://perma.cc/NH7B-MW29] (commenting that the change is primarily driven by relative weakness in patentability requirements and patent opposition and noting that all other EU countries patent opposition system scored higher than that of the United States). In 2020, the U.S. IP system ranking went back up according to the 2020 International IP Index. See U.S. Chamber of Com., Glob. Innovation Pol’y Ctr., U.S. Chamber International IP Index 38 (8th ed. 2020), https://www.uschamber.com/assets/documents/023881_gipc_ip_index_2020_fullreport_final.pdf [https:
//perma.cc/Y2KQ-9NH2].

          [5].      Subcomm. on Intell. Prop., Innovation in America: How Congress Can Make Our Patent System STRONGER, Comm. on Judiciary (Sept. 11, 2019, 2:30 PM), https://www.judiciary.senate.gov/
meetings/innovation-in-america-how-congress-can-make-our-patent-system-stronger [https://perma.cc/
KW4C-2M2J] (broadcasted at 1:53; Senator Tillis urging Director Iancu to make administrative changes to the PTAB). 

*      Executive Editor, Southern California Law Review, Volume 95; J.D. Candidate 2022, University of Southern California Gould School of Law; B.S. Mechanical Engineering, B.S. Earth Science, Rice University. I would like to thank Yoko Hongyu Li for her invaluable guidance on data gathering and software programming. To my parents Xiao and Wei, thank you for encouraging me in all my pursuits and inspiring me to follow my dreams. Finally, many thanks to editors at Southern California Law Review who made this process a breeze.

Time to Go Auer Separate Ways: Why the Bia Should not Say What the Law is by Tatum Rosenfeld

Note | Immigration Law
Time to Go Auer Separate Ways: Why the BIA Should Not Say What the Law is
by Tatum P. Rosenfeld*

From Vol. 94, No. 5 (2021)
94 S. Cal. L. Rev. 1279 (2021)

Keywords: Board of Immigration Appeals (“BIA”), Auer

Neither fully legislative nor fully judicial, federal administrative agencies are tasked with “policing the minutiae.”1 They codify and enforce the details of the regulatory scheme set out by Congress.2 Simply put, administrative agencies administer the law. Agency regulations, however, like other legal sources, can be ambiguous.3 Thus, interpretation is inevitably necessary either to confront a novel circumstance or to resolve an inherent semantic ambiguity. This then raises the question: Who should be called upon to resolve such ambiguities? The Supreme Court’s solution is to put agencies in charge. Auer deference says an agency’s interpretation of its own rule controls so long as it is not “plainly erroneous or inconsistent with the regulation.”4 In effect, after an agency promulgates a regulation, it then maintains the latitude to fill in the gaps by interpreting its own regulation.

The Court has offered no good reason why Auer, while reasonable in some situations, should be applied indiscriminately to all agencies. A multitude of federal agencies exist to effectuate policies touching on everything under the sun—including housing, education, social benefits, food, agriculture, commerce, health, and the environment—but there is one agency in particular whose special attributes suggest that it should not be treated the same as all the others. That is the agency in charge of immigration appeals. One might reasonably think deference, for example, to the Food and Drug Administration’s expert interpretation of what constitutes an “active moiety,” promotes a robust and efficient government necessary for modern complexities. It follows that such agencies deserve deference from a court that is less well versed in the expertise involved in rendering such a judgment. However, immigration presents an entirely different set of policy concerns. 

This is because deference to the Board of Immigration Appeals (“BIA”) under Auer risks political manipulation at the expense of immigrants’ liberty and freedom. Nested under the Department of Justice (“DOJ”), and more specifically the Executive Office of Immigration Review (“EOIR”), the BIA and lower immigration courts operate as quasi-judicial bodies, specifically “prone to political manipulation because of their unique combination of structure, history, and function.”A “clarifing” interpretation by the BIA can dictate the scheme by which people are welcomed into or rejected from the United States. The BIA is the unsuspecting gatekeeper, capable of molding the rules by interpretation to advance an anti-immigrant political agenda. Auer, therefore, acts as another tool in the political toolbox to restrict immigration in what is already a labyrinth of proceedings, paperwork, and fear.

This Note argues that Auer deference, even in light of the Supreme Court’s recent clarification of the doctrine, is an inappropriate approach for courts to take when they review the BIA’s rulings. Because the BIA lacks political accountability while simultaneously commingling government powers, deference to the BIA undermines key constitutional principles, such as separation of powers and democracy. Such principles must be enhanced, rather than undermined, more than ever when there is a heightened threat to
liberty. Therefore, a close look is needed to determine whether
Auer deference is warranted for an agency in which the very freedoms of immigrants are at stake. 
The problem actually goes even further. Even if federal courts decided to eschew deference to BIA interpretations, the courts’ own interpretations would still not be an adequate mechanism to protect immigrants from unjust results. With ever-growing caseloads, Article III judges are not equipped with the requisite resources, time, and experience with immigration laws to adjudicate thousands more life-altering decisions in a timely, just manner.Immigration matters deserve to be adjudicated with proper accountability and more formalistic separations of power than those that currently stand. To achieve this, immigration courts and the BIA should, as many others have suggested before, be reformulated as Article I legislative courts to best serve democratic and separation of powers purposes. Liberty for immigrants can be salvaged through fairer adjudications and independent interpretations that are more insulated from political manipulation and the polarized ideologies that waft in and out of power.

This Note proceeds as follows: Part I briefly details a background of the BIA, and a current understanding of Auer deference. This discussion includes Auer’s political implications, and how the Supreme Court chose not to overrule the doctrine in Kisor v. Wilkie. This Section then explores the relationship between Auer and the BIA, including why the BIA’s political vulnerability makes the agency particularly unfit for Auer deference. Certain appointees to this agency have been rewarded with a position as a board member by openly declaring their hostility to the very people who are the object of the agency’s mission, and whose fragile life prospects are in their hands. Ironically, this flips the partisan commitments normally seen in the world of administrative law as follows: Those who would classically support increasing agency discretion by according Auer deference should be worried about giving heightened power to the self-declared, anti-immigrant agenda pervading the BIA, while those who would classically resist excessive delegation and deference to agencies, because of their limited accountability, seek to endow the BIA with vast independence and partisan manipulation. Part II argues that even in the wake of Kisor v. Wilkie, deference to the BIA’s interpretations of immigration regulations presents a heightened threat to constitutional principles of separation of powers and democracy. Part III then provides a potential solution to the inadequacy of Auer deference and the judicial role in the realm of regulatory gap filling for immigration laws. 
 

* Executive Development Editor, Southern California Law Review, Volume 94; J.D. Candidate 2021, University of Southern California Gould School of Law; B.A., 2017, University of Michigan, Communications and Minor in Law, Justice & Social Change. I am so deeply grateful for my family and their unending support, especially my dad for always being my sounding board and biggest cheerleader. I want to thank Professor Rebecca L. Brown for her invaluable guidance and inspiring perspective in drafting this Note. And, thank you to the talented Southern California Law Review staff and editors for their thoughtful work throughout this publication process.

[maxbutton id=”2″ url=”https://southerncalifornialawreview.com/wp-content/uploads/2022/02/Rosenfeld_Final.pdf” window=”new”  

The Supersecretary in Chief

Postscript | Administrative Law
The Supersecretary in Chief
by Kathryn E. Kovacs*

Vol. 94, Postscript (November 2020)
94 S. Cal. L. Rev. Postscript 61 (2020)

Keywords: Administrative Procedure Act, Unitary executive theory

Introduction

The U.S. President plays many roles. Under the Constitution, the President acts as Commander in Chief when directing the military,[1] “Legislator in Chief” when exercising the President’s functions in the legislative process,[2] and Negotiator in Chief under the Treaty Clause.[3] The President acts as the “Statutory President” when exercising authority delegated to the Office of the President by statute,[4] for example, when controlling immigration, establishing tariffs, and declaring emergencies.[5] As head of the executive branch, the President often acts as “Administrator in Chief,” guiding the federal officers who are charged by statute with implementing the law.[6]

This essay concerns situations in which the President goes beyond guiding those officers and actually exercises their statutory authority, essentially acting as a higher-level officer. I dub the President in this capacity the Supersecretary in Chief.[7] President Trump, for example, decided to “permit [liquefied natural gas] to be transported in approved rail tank cars,”[8] even though a federal statute delegates that safety determination to the Secretary of Transportation.[9] Similarly, both Presidents Obama and Trump dictated immigration enforcement policies, even though a federal statute assigns enforcement discretion to the Secretary of Homeland Security.[10] As Kathryn Watts observed, “presidential control . . . has become woven into the fabric of the regulatory state, and it occurs regardless of the political party in the White House.”[11]

The unitary executive theory blesses this state of affairs as an accurate reflection of Article II. The Constitution vests the executive power in the President, the argument goes; therefore, all exercises of executive power are within the President’s purview.[12] Accordingly, the Constitution gives the President the inherent power not only to influence the actions of the officials to whom Congress has assigned statutory authority, but also to step into their shoes and direct their actions, nullify their actions, or take action in their stead, even in areas in which the President otherwise has no constitutional power.[13]

Focusing on the Supersecretary in Chief demonstrates that the unitary executive theory is wrong, because allowing the President to exercise functions that Congress assigned to another officer shifts the balance of powers between the three branches of government.[14] First, the legitimacy of congressional delegations of power to federal officers is premised on control of those officers. Yet, unlike other federal officers, the President is not subject to such control. Second, Congress delegates authority to agencies on the understanding that the agencies will implement their statutory authority via Administrative Procedure Act (“APA”) processes and face judicial review.[15] Under the Supreme Court’s decision in Franklin v. Massachusetts, however, the President does not follow the APA and is not subject to full judicial review.[16] Third, the President’s duty to execute the law faithfully requires the President to implement Congress’s choices regarding the scope of the statutory delegation, the required procedure, and the identity of the delegate. The Supersecretary in Chief does not do so. Given those significant constitutional costs, the unitary executive theory’s approval of the Supersecretary in Chief casts serious doubt on the theory. It should be abandoned, and the President should not be permitted to act as Supersecretary in Chief.

Unfortunately, neither Congress nor the courts have reined in the Supersecretary in Chief, which leads me to explore alternative approaches to correcting the current imbalance. One possible alternative is the APA. Treating the Supersecretary in Chief like an “agency” under the APA would restore some balance by subjecting the President to Congress’s and the courts’ control, reinstating Congress’s primacy in drafting statutes, and faithfully executing the law—at least to some extent.[17] Unfortunately, the APA cannot solve the balance-of-powers problem entirely because it does not erase the fact that the President as Supersecretary in Chief supplants Congress’s chosen delegate. At most, the APA is a second-best alternative to simply striking down any presidential effort to bypass statutory delegations.

I. The President as Supersecretary in Chief

Congress often enacts statutes delegating decisionmaking responsibility to federal officers who lead administrative agencies in the executive branch. There is little dispute that the President, as head of the executive branch, may “be involved in agency decisions such as rulemaking.”[18] Beyond that, however, there is much debate. Under the standard view, the President cannot go so far as to “dictate actions to officials that Congress has authorized to act.”[19] If a presidentially appointed official takes action with which the President disagrees, the President’s primary legal recourse is to remove that person from office.[20]

The unitary executive theory contradicts the standard view. It posits that the Constitution assigns the executive power—“all of it,” as the Court recently emphasized[21]—to the President alone.[22] Any officer the President appoints merely helps the President exercise that constitutional authority.[23] Thus, the President is not limited to merely influencing the officials to whom Congress has delegated statutory authority. Rather, the Constitution gives the President the implied power to dictate their decisions or step into their shoes to exercise their authority, even in areas in which the President has no constitutional power.[24] In other words, the President may act as a higher level officer—as a Supersecretary.

Despite years of cautionary scholarship,[25] the unitary executive theory is now a reality.[26] As Daniel Farber observed, “recent presidents of both parties ‘have publicly proclaimed their authority to direct the administration of the federal government,’ with George W. Bush famously calling himself ‘the decider’ and Barack Obama saying, ‘I’ve got a pen to take executive actions where Congress won’t.’ ”[27] Presidents now direct agency actions via executive order, memorandum, and even tweet.[28] They do this not only in the military and national security arena where the President’s power is primary, but in areas in which Congress has constitutional primacy and has assigned policymaking authority to a particular officer.[29] Presidents are overriding Congress’s chosen delegate to act as the Supersecretary in Chief.

For example, President Obama took credit in a YouTube video for the Clean Power Plan,[30] a rule that the Clean Air Act authorized the Administrator of the Environmental Protection Agency (“EPA”) to issue.[31] President Trump mandated its rescission in an executive order.[32]

The Immigration and Nationality Act delegates enforcement discretion to the Secretary of Homeland Security.[33] Nonetheless, President Obama announced a new immigration enforcement policy in the Rose Garden; the Secretary of Homeland Security then promulgated it in a memorandum.[34] Five days after his inauguration, President Trump issued an executive order directing his new Secretary to rescind that policy and prescribing new enforcement priorities for the Department.[35]

President Trump has provided numerous other examples of this phenomenon.[36] He:

  • ordered the Army Corps of Engineers to “approve in an expedited manner” the Dakota Access Pipeline,[37] even though the relevant statutes delegate decisionmaking authority to the Secretaries of the Army and Interior[38];
  • ordered the EPA “to take specific actions to ensure efficient and cost-effective implementation” of the Clean Air Act[39] and to revise its Clean Water Act regulations to minimize the ability of states and tribes to interfere with the approval of energy projects,[40] despite the fact that both of those statutes empower the Administrator of the EPA to make such decisions[41];
  • ordered the Secretaries of the Interior, Agriculture, and Commerce to renew expired rights-of-way for energy infrastructure,[42] although the relevant statutes assign that responsibility to those particular officers[43];
  • ordered the Secretaries of Agriculture and the Interior to pursue active forest management,[44] overriding the statutes that entrust such judgments to those officers[45];
  • ordered the Secretaries of Treasury, Agriculture, Commerce, Labor, Health and Human Services, Housing and Urban Development, Transportation, and Education to amend their regulations to require recipients of public assistance to seek employment,[46] although typically the relevant statutes assign rulemaking responsibility to the Secretaries[47];
  • ordered the Secretary of Labor to revise the regulations governing multiple employer retirement plans,[48] even though Congress delegated that authority to the Secretary[49]; and
  • ordered agencies to revise their regulations governing commercial use of space[50] and established a detailed policy on the management of traffic in space[51] although statutes already assigned those responsibilities to the National Aeronautic and Space Administration and the Secretary of Transportation, among others.[52]

Numerous other statutes order federal officers to implement their provisions in regulations. Yet, President Trump issued an executive order forcing those officers to repeal two regulations for every one promulgated,[53] thus “constraining the authority of regulatory agencies to implement those statutes consistent with their express purposes and goals.”[54] Trump’s handling of the COVID-19 pandemic provides numerous other examples of this phenomenon.[55]

Even where a President does not go so far as to dictate a particular regulatory outcome, the President’s influence may be so strong that the agency effectively is prevented from exercising its statutorily delegated discretion. For example, President Trump issued an executive order regarding the rule interpreting the term “waters of the United States” in the Clean Water Act.[56] He ordered the Army Corps of Engineers and the EPA to rescind or revise the existing rule and consider making the new rule “consistent with the opinion of Justice Antonin Scalia in Rapanos v. United States, 547 U.S. 715 (2006).”[57] Technically, the President left the decision to the Army Secretary and EPA Administrator, but his order “tilt[ed] the agencies” toward Scalia’s view.[58] Following the President’s wishes in such an order must be a major motivation for any final agency decision.[59] Indeed, the agencies’ notice of intent to revise the rule specifically referenced the President’s “directive” as its motivation,[60] and the final rule followed Justice Scalia’s Rapanos opinion.[61] Even without a direct order, the President displaced Congress’s chosen delegate.

In sum, where before agencies would make policy decisions with more or less presidential influence, Presidents now make policy decisions with more or less agency involvement.[62]

One difficulty with this state of affairs is that Presidents do not follow the procedures required of agencies, and they are not subject to judicial review to same extent as agencies.[63] Before issuing any binding policy statement, an agency must give notice of its proposal, accept and consider public comments, and publish the final rule with an explanation for its decision.[64] The President need not follow any particular procedure before issuing a binding directive.[65] If an agency’s decision is challenged in court, it must produce an administrative record for the court to use when determining whether the action was “arbitrary, capricious, an abuse of discretion, or otherwise not in accordance with law.”[66] Presidential decisions cannot be reviewed under that standard,[67] and presidential documents generally are not included in administrative records.[68]

Despite the inadequate procedure and judicial review, presidential policy decisions are all binding to some degree.[69] A presidential order, like an agency rule, can have the force of law even if it binds only an executive branch agency[70] and even if it is not enforceable in court.[71] The Department of Justice now takes the position that even the President’s Tweets are official statements of the President.[72] Both agencies[73] and courts have treated them as binding.[74]

II. Unbalancing the Balance of Powers

Allowing the President to exercise authority that a statute assigns to another officer impermissibly shifts the balance of power between the branches of government. The unitary executive theory blesses this state of affairs. As explained above,[75] the unitary executive theory holds that “[w]henever an official is granted statutory discretion, the Constitution endows the President with the authority to control that discretion.”[76] Others have explained some of the flaws in that theory.[77] Focusing on the Supersecretary in Chief reveals flaws that the existing critiques have not highlighted. The unitary executive theory’s endorsement of the Supersecretary in Chief, despite the significant constitutional problems with the President bypassing Congress’s chosen delegate, further demonstrates that unitary executive theory is wrong.

The balance-of-powers concept “stresses the need to balance the departments of government, primarily through the creation and maintenance of tension and competition among them.”[78] As James Madison observed in Federalist No. 51, each part of the government must be given “the necessary constitutional means and personal motives to resist encroachments of the others.”[79] M. Elizabeth Magill correctly highlighted the indeterminacy of this concept.[80] At its core, though, the balance-of-powers concept rejects any effort to usurp one branch’s constitutional checks on the others[81] and views with skepticism efforts to reduce the level of tension and competition between the branches.[82]

The President acting as Supersecretary in Chief violates that concept in at least three interrelated ways. First, the legitimacy of statutory delegations of decisionmaking authority to agencies is premised on control of those agencies.[83] The APA codified the conditions for that legitimacy. As I explained elsewhere, “[t]he APA represents a constitutional moment following years of meaningful democratic deliberation. At that moment, Congress, the President, and the courts unanimously accepted the existence of the administrative state, conditioned on procedural constraints and judicial review.”[84] The APA’s requirements “were the necessary ‘quid pro quos’ for the creation of the administrative state.”[85]

The President, however, is not subject to such control, because Franklin v. Massachusetts held that the APA does not apply to the President.[86] Consequently, the President may take action using solely statutory authority without any procedural restraint or adequate judicial review.[87] This undermines Congress’s and the courts’ ability to control the exercise of statutory delegations, shifting the balance of power decidedly in the President’s favor. “When the President assumes policymaking power without policymaking constraints, it undermines the central bargain of the APA and shakes the foundation upon which the administrative state is built.”[88]

Second, Congress delegates authority to officers on the understanding that the officers will implement their statutory authority via APA procedures and face judicial review.[89] Attorney General Wirt observed in 1823 that “[t]he Constitution assigns to Congress the power of designating the duties of particular officers.”[90] The Constitution also assigns to Congress the power of specifying the procedures by which officers act.[91] In fact, even where statutes assign rulemaking authority to the Office of the President, Congress may subject that authority to “substantive or procedural constraints.”[92] In other words, Congress may constrain presidential “value judgments in order to effectuate the execution of the law it creates.”[93] Allowing the President to exercise statutory authority without satisfying Congress’s statutory conditions contradicts Congress’s intent and undermines the legislative bargains underlying the statutory delegations, effectively usurping Congress’s lawmaking power.[94] It “cloth[es] the President with a power entirely to control the legislation of Congress”[95] and is “inconsistent with a fundamental design principle reflected in our evolved constitutional order.”[96]

Proponents of the unitary executive theory might object that Congress also delegates with the understanding that the President has the power to control federal officers, and thus, all statutory delegations to federal officers include the potential for a presidential override.[97] On the contrary, members of Congress may not agree with unitary executive theory.[98] They may recognize that “the Vesting Clause only speaks to the issue of who has control of this executive power to implement the laws. It does not speak to what the laws require in terms of substance or how to implement them in terms of process.”[99] They may understand that the President’s executive power must coexist with Congress’s power “to make all laws necessary and proper” for executing the powers vested in the federal government “or in any Department or Officer thereof.”[100] They may believe that Congress plays a “central role in structuring the Executive Branch,” and “[t]he President, as to the construction of his own branch of government, can only try to work his will through the legislative process.”[101] Robert Percival showed that “every regulatory review program since the rise of the administrative state has been founded on the notion that the president did not have the authority to displace agency decisionmaking.”[102] As Percival pointed out, some statutes expressly allow the President to override agency decisions, which undermines any inference that Congress intends to allow the President to override agencies in other circumstances.[103]

Third, the President’s duty to execute the law faithfully requires the President to implement the choices Congress and the President jointly etched in statutes.[104] Like a fiduciary, the President “must diligently and steadily execute Congress’s commands.”[105] Thus, the President must implement Congress’s choices regarding the scope of the statutory delegation, the required procedure, and the identity of the delegate.[106] When the President executes quintessentially presidential functions—commanding the armed forces, negotiating treaties, etc.—one might argue that legislative restrictions are inappropriate. On the other hand, when the President performs functions that Congress delegated to another officer—when the President acts as Supersecretary in Chief—legislative restrictions are part of the law that the President must execute.[107] Failing to do so impermissibly shifts the balance of powers toward the President.

III.  The APA to the Rescue?

In the absence of congressional or judicial action to rein in the Supersecretary in Chief, the APA provides a means of restoring some balance between the branches. I demonstrated elsewhere that the President should be subject to the APA when exercising powers assigned by statute to the Office of the President; in other words, the Statutory President should be treated like an “agency” under the APA.[108] I explained how the Supreme Court misread the APA’s text and contradicted its history when it held to the contrary in Franklin v. Massachusetts.[109] I revealed the flaws in the Court’s constitutional analysis: contrary to Franklin, treating the Statutory President like an “agency” under the APA alleviates the constitutional concerns with the President making binding policy decisions unilaterally.[110] I also presented the normative case for treating the Statutory President like any other agency under the APA.[111] Finally, I sketched a model for applying the APA to the Statutory President using Trump v. Hawaii as a foil.[112] I did not address the question of whether the President should be subject to the APA when exercising another officer’s statutory authority.[113] That is my task here.

If the APA applied to the Supersecretary in Chief, before making a binding decision, the President would have to give public notice of the proposed policy and accept and consider public comments.[114] The President would have to provide an explanation for the final decision.[115] Finally, the federal courts could review the record of materials the President considered in reaching a final decision[116] to determine if the decision is “arbitrary, capricious, an abuse of discretion, or otherwise not in accordance with law.”[117]

Applying these APA requirements to the Supersecretary in Chief would alleviate the balance-of-powers problems with the Supersecretary in Chief’s usurpation of another officer’s statutory authority. It also would advance the APA’s normative goals—public participation, political accountability, transparency, deliberation, and uniformity.[118] It would make the President’s decisionmaking more transparent to Congress and the public and subject it to court oversight, thus allowing some control and enhancing political accountability.[119] It also might improve the quality of the President’s decisions, enhance the fairness of the President’s decisionmaking process, and promote deliberation, making it more likely that the President’s decisions will reflect the public interest and expertise rather than raw politics.[120]

Applying the APA to the Supersecretary in Chief would only partially respect Congress’s lawmaking power and faithfully execute the law. The difficulty would remain that the President, when acting as Supersecretary in Chief, supplants Congress’s chosen delegate. Thus, in this context, the APA is only a second-best alternative.[121] If Presidents continue their march down unitary executive theory lane, though, better a second-best alternative than none.[122] Moreover, employing the APA to partially remedy the constitutional difficulties with the Supersecretary in Chief may be less intrusive than forcing the issue in court.[123]

Unfortunately, this means of restoring the balance of powers presents practical difficulties when applied to the Supersecretary in Chief. The Statutory President is designated by statute as the final decisionmaker.[124] Thus, the Statutory President’s decisions generally appear in definitive, written documents.[125] In contrast, when acting as Supersecretary in Chief, the President may employ a range of devices to control officers’ exercises of statutory power from expressly co-opting or directing an officer’s decision to subtly nudging, massaging, facilitating, or encouraging a particular outcome.[126] Subjecting only the more obvious instances of presidential control to the APA could incentivize the President to shift to less obvious means of control.[127] That could drive presidential influence underground where Congress, the courts, and the public cannot even monitor it, much less control it.[128] Expanding the APA’s application to all presidential influence on agency exercises of statutory authority would require documenting all presidential contact (both direct and indirect) with decisionmaking officers, making that material available for public notice and comment, and including it all in the record for judicial review.[129] Such a rule would be difficult to implement and impossible to enforce; any effort in that direction could drive presidential control even further underground.

Yet, driving presidential influence underground would be better than the current trajectory toward unmasked authoritarianism. Presidential influence is constitutionally acceptable so long as it does not prevent the deciding officer from exercising their statutorily delegated discretion.[130] Underground influence may be less likely to cross that line. It leaves Congress’s chosen delegates to make the decisions and take responsibility for them. Those officers are far more transparent and accountable than the President.[131] They engage the public and deliberate more than the President.[132] And they have the institutional support and expertise to make higher quality decisions than the President.[133] In any event, absent an order from the Supersecretary in Chief, the officer’s decision will stand or fall on its own merits under the APA’s arbitrary or capricious standard of review.[134] That is preferable to the overly deferential review of presidential orders.[135]

Conclusion

Unitary executive theory endorses a shift in the balance of powers away from the courts and Congress and towards the President.[136] Opposition to that shift should be bipartisan.[137] Conservatives decried President Obama’s unilateral actions, and now progressives bemoan President Trump’s.[138] The President should not be permitted to act as Supersecretary in Chief, lest the growing power of the presidency destroy our democratic republic.

In the absence of direct opposition to the growth of presidential power, however, the APA provides a second-best alternative. Treating the Supersecretary in Chief like an “agency” under the APA would partially alleviate the constitutional problems with the President supplanting Congress’s statutory delegates. It also would enhance public participation, political accountability, transparency, deliberation, and uniformity, leading the President to make better decisions. That is in every American’s interest.


          [1].      U.S. Const. art. II, § 2, cl. 1. See generally Zachary Price, Congress’s Power Over Military Offices, 99 Tex. L. Rev. (forthcoming), https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=3550548 [https://perma.cc/JRD7-Q2C2] (exploring the scope of congressional and presidential authority over military officers).

          [2].      See Vasan Kesavan & J. Gregory Sidak, The Legislator-in-Chief, 44 Wm. & Mary L. Rev. 1, 4 (2002).

          [3].      U.S. Const. art. II, § 2, cl. 2.

          [4].      Kevin M. Stack, The Statutory President, 90 Iowa L. Rev. 539, 542 (2005).

          [5].      See Kathryn E. Kovacs, Constraining the Statutory President, 98 Wash. U. L. Rev. 62 (2020).

          [6].      See Ming H. Chen, Administrator-in-Chief: The President and Executive Action in Immigration Law, 69 Admin. L. Rev. 347, 358–59 (2017). Others use the term “Administrator in Chief” to refer to the President “as a central figure directing agencies’ implementation of statutes.” Bijal Shah, Congress’s Agency Coordination, 103 Minn. L. Rev. 1961, 1963 n.5 (2019) (citing references). I use the term here to refer to the President as the administrative head of the executive branch, as distinguished from the President as the decisionmaker or Supersecretary in Chief.

          [7].      See Super, Merriam-Webster, https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/super [https://
perma.cc/Y7TN-VE83] (defining the prefix “super” as “situated or placed above, on, or at the top of”).

          [8].      Exec. Order No. 13,868, 84 Fed. Reg. 15,495, 15497 § 4(b) (Apr. 10, 2019) (“The Secretary of Transportation shall propose for notice and comment a rule . . . that would . . . permit LNG to be transported in approved rail tank cars. The Secretary shall finalize such rulemaking no later than 13 months after the date of this order.”).

          [9].      49 U.S.C. § 60102.

        [10].      See infra text accompanying notes 33–35.

        [11].      Kathryn A. Watts, Controlling Presidential Control, 114 Mich. L. Rev. 683, 726 (2016).

        [12].      Kathryn E. Kovacs, Rules About Rulemaking and the Rise of the Unitary Executive, 70 Admin. L. Rev. 515, 562 (2018); see also Seila Law LLC v. Consumer Fin. Prot. Bureau, 140 S. Ct. 2183, 2191 (2020) (“Under our Constitution, the ‘executive Power’—all of it—is ‘vested in a President’. . . .” (quoting U.S. Const. art. II, §1, cl. 1)).

        [13].      See Stack, supra note 4, at 583 (canvassing proponents of a strong unitary executive theory); see also Steven G. Calabresi & Saikrishna B. Prakash, The President’s Power to Execute the Laws, 104 Yale L.J. 541, 593–99 (1994); Steven G. Calabresi & Kevin H. Rhodes, The Structural Constitution: Unitary Executive, Plural Judiciary, 105 Harv. L. Rev. 1153, 1166 (1992); Gary Lawson, The Rise and Rise of the Administrative State, 107 Harv. L. Rev. 1231, 1242–43 (1994); Christopher S. Yoo, Steven G. Calabresi & Anthony J. Colangelo, The Unitary Executive in the Modern Era, 1945–2004, 90 Iowa L. Rev. 601, 607 (2005).

        [14].      See infra Part II.

        [15].      Administrative Procedure Act, Pub. L. No. 79–404, 60 Stat. 237 (1946).

        [16].      Franklin v. Massachusetts, 505 U.S. 788, 800–01 (1992).

        [17].      See infra Part III.

        [18].     Nina A. Mendelson, Disclosing “Political” Oversight of Agency Decision Making, 108 Mich. L. Rev. 1127, 1131 (2010).

        [19].      Mark Seidenfeld, A Process-Based Approach to Presidential Exit, 67 Duke L.J. 1775, 1781 (2018); see also Harold H. Bruff, Presidential Management of Agency Rulemaking, 57 Geo. Wash. L. Rev. 533, 539 (1989) (“[T]he President may not simply render a decision himself when Congress has vested such authority in another officer.”); William W. Buzbee, The Tethered President: Consistency and Contingency in Administrative Law, 98 B.U. L. Rev. 1357, 1363 (2018) (“[P]olicy shifts cannot be carried out by executive fiat.”); Robert V. Percival, Presidential Management of the Administrative State: The Not-So-Unitary Executive, 51 Duke L.J. 963, 965 (2001) (the “conventional wisdom is that the President does not have” “the power to dictate the substance of regulatory decisions that agencies are required by law to make”); Robert V. Percival, Who’s in Charge? Does the President Have Directive Authority over Agency Regulatory Decisions?, 79 Fordham L. Rev. 2487, 2538 (2011) (“the view most accepted by scholars is that the President does not” have “the legal authority to dictate the substance of regulatory decisions entrusted by statute to agency heads”); Peter L. Strauss, Overseer, or “The Decider”? The President in Administrative Law, 75 Geo. Wash. L. Rev. 696, 705–06 (2007).

        [20].      Bruff, supra note 19, at 539; Richard J. Pierce, Jr., Saving the Unitary Executive Theory from Those Who Would Distort and Abuse It: A Review of The Unitary Executive by Steven G. Calabresi and Christopher S. Yoo, 12 U. Pa. J. Const. L. 593, 613 (2010) (“I do not believe that the President has the power to veto a decision made by an executive officer to whom Congress has delegated the decision. If the President disagrees with such a decision his only recourse is to remove the officer.”).

        [21].      Seila Law LLC v. Consumer Fin. Prot. Bureau, 140 S. Ct. 2183, 2191 (2020).

        [22].      Kovacs, supra note 12, at 562.

        [23].      Calabresi & Prakash, supra note 13, at 596 (“[T]he Constitution establishes that the President exclusively controls the power to execute all federal laws, and therefore it must be the case that all inferior executive officers act in his stead.”) (emphasis omitted); Saikrishna Bangalore Prakash, Hail to the Chief Administrator: The Framers and the President’s Administrative Powers, 102 Yale L.J. 991, 991–94 (1993) (similar); Peter M. Shane, Madison’s Nightmare: How Executive Power Threatens American Democracy 34, 37, 145 (2009) (explaining the unitary executive theory).

        [24].      See Stack, supra note 4, at 583 (canvassing proponents of a strong unitary executive theory); see also Calabresi & Prakash, supra note 13, at 593–99; Calabresi & Rhodes, supra note 13, at 1166; Lawson, supra note 13, at 1242–43; Yoo et al., supra note 13, at 607.

        [25].      See, e.g., Buzbee, supra note 19; Thomas O. McGarity, Presidential Control of Regulatory Agency Decisionmaking, 36 Am. U. L. Rev. 443 (1987); Mark Seidenfeld, The Role of Politics in a Deliberative Model of the Administrative State, 81 Geo. Wash. L. Rev. 1397 (2013); Strauss, supra note 19.

        [26].      See Kovacs, supra note 12, at 562; Jerry L. Mashaw & David Berke, Presidential Administration in A Regime of Separated Powers: An Analysis of Recent American Experience, 35 Yale J. on Reg. 549, 551 (2018) (studying the growth of presidential control in the Obama and Trump administrations); Watts, supra note 11, at 729 (“Presidential directive authority with respect to executive agencies is alive and well.”); Christopher S. Yoo, Foreword, 12 U. Pa. J. Const. L. 241, 243 (2010) (“The consistency with which the last several administrations have embraced centralized control over the administration of federal law eloquently demonstrates how the unitary executive has gained general acceptance.”); cf. Gillian E. Metzger, Foreword: 1930s Redux: The Administrative State Under Siege, 131 Harv. L. Rev. 1, 75 (2017) (“[P]residential administration has become the central reality of the contemporary national government.”).

        [27].      Daniel A. Farber, Presidential Administration Under Trump 23 (Aug. 9, 2017) (unpublished manuscript) https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=3015591 [https://perma.cc/SD5X-RM
HM]; see also Douglas H. Ginsburg & Steven Menashi, Nondelegation and the Unitary Executive, 12 U. Pa. J. Const. L. 251, 274–75 (2010) (detailing President Obama’s “principal strategies to strengthen his control over the executive”).

        [28].      See Knight First Amendment Inst. at Columbia Univ. v. Trump, 302 F. Supp. 3d 541, 571 (S.D.N.Y. 2018), aff’d, 928 F.3d 226 (2d Cir. 2019) (quoting stipulation that President Trump uses Twitter “to announce, describe, and defend his policies . . . [and] to announce official decisions”); J.B. Ruhl & James Salzman, Presidential Exit, 67 Duke L.J. 1729, 1739–41 (2018). See generally Phillip J. Cooper, By Order of the President: The Use and Abuse of Executive Direct Action (2d ed. 2014).

        [29].      See Lisa Manheim & Kathryn A. Watts, Reviewing Presidential Orders, 86 U. Chi. L. Rev. 1743, 1745, 1762, 1766–69 (2019).

        [30].      The Obama White House, President Obama on America’s Clean Power Plan, YouTube (Aug. 2, 2015), https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=uYXyYFzP4Lc [https://perma.cc/5EAD-BNF3]. See generally Jud Mathews, Presidential Administration in the Obama Era, in The U.S. Supreme Court And Contemporary Constitutional Law: The Obama Era And Its Legacy 67 (Anna-Bettina Kaiser, Niels Petersen & Johannes Saurer eds., 2019) (discussing presidentialism in the Obama administration).

        [31].      Carbon Pollution Emission Guidelines for Existing Stationary Sources: Electric Utility Generating Units, 80 Fed. Reg. 64,662 (Oct. 23, 2015) (promulgated under 42 U.S.C. § 7411(d), which delegates rulemaking authority to the EPA Administrator).

        [32].      Exec. Order No. 13,783, 82 Fed. Reg. 16,093 (Mar. 28, 2017).

        [33].      8 U.S.C. § 1103(a).

        [34].      Memorandum from Janet Napolitano, Sec’y of Homeland Sec., to David V. Aguilar, Acting Comm’r, U.S. Customs & Border Prot. et al. (June 15, 2012), https://www.dhs.gov/xlibrary/assets/s1-exercising-prosecutorial-discretion-individuals-who-came-to-us-as-children.pdf [https://perma.cc/U5RD
-6XLA]; see also Manheim & Watts, supra note 29, at 1787 (“[T]he DAPA order in some ways felt like an executive order.”).

        [35].      Exec. Order No. 13,768, 82 Fed. Reg. 8,799 (Jan. 25, 2017).

        [36].      Manheim & Watts, supra note 29, at 1786 (“Trump has acted aggressively throughout his presidency to blur the lines between the President and the agencies he oversees.”).

        [37].      Construction of the Dakota Access Pipeline, Memorandum for the Secretary of the Army, 82 Fed. Reg. 11,129 (Jan. 24, 2017); see also Buzbee, supra note 19, at 1389.

        [38].      The President referenced the Mineral Leasing Act, which delegates authority to the Secretary of the Interior, 30 U.S.C. § 185(a), and the Clean Water Act and the Rivers and Harbors Act, which delegate authority to the Secretary of the Army, 33 U.S.C. §§ 408, 1344.

        [39].      Presidential Memorandum for the Administrator of the Environmental Protection Agency (Apr. 12, 2018), https://www.whitehouse.gov/presidential-actions/presidential-memorandum-administra
tor-environmental-protection-agency [https://perma.cc/57E6-8TU9].

        [40].      Exec. Order No. 13,868, 84 Fed. Reg. 15,495, 15,495 § 3 (Apr. 10, 2019).

        [41].      42 U.S.C. § 7410; 33 U.S.C. § 1341.

        [42].      Exec. Order No. 13,868, 84 Fed. Reg. 15,495, 15,497 § 6(b) (Apr. 10, 2019).

        [43].      See U.S. Dep’t of Energy, Quadrennial Energy Review: Energy Transmission, Storage, and Distribution Infrastructure ch. IX (Apr. 2015), https://www.energy.gov/sites/prod/

files/2015/04/f22/QER-ALL%20FINAL_0.pdf [https://perma.cc/Q6RK-F9QK].

        [44].      Exec. Order No. 13,855, 84 Fed. Reg. 45 (Dec. 21, 2018). Many of these presidential orders include boilerplate statements that they should be “implemented consistent with applicable law and subject to the availability of appropriations.” E.g., id § 7(b); Exec. Order No. 13,868 § 10(b). That language does not prevent Presidents from ordering officers to take specific actions.

        [45].      E.g., 16 U.S.C. § 529; 43 U.S.C. §§ 1701, 1732.

        [46].      Exec. Order 13,828, 83 Fed. Reg. 15,941, 15,943 § 3 (Apr. 10, 2018).

        [47].      E.g., 7 U.S.C. § 2015(b)(4) (Supplemental Nutrition Assistance Program); 42 U.S.C. § 607 (b)(3)(A) (Temporary Assistance for Needy Families).

        [48].      Exec. Order 13,847, 83 Fed. Reg. 45,321 (Aug. 31, 2018).

        [49].      29 U.S.C. § 1135.

        [50].      Streamlining Regulations on Commercial Use of Space, Space Policy Directive-2, 83 Fed. Reg., 24,901 (May 24, 2018).

        [51].      Space Policy Directive-3, National Space Traffic Management Policy, 83 Fed. Reg. 28,969 (June 18, 2018).

        [52].      E.g., 51 U.S.C. §§ 20113(a), 50905(b)(2).

        [53].      Exec. Order No. 13,771, 82 Fed. Reg. 9,339 (Jan. 30, 2017); see also Buzbee, supra note 19, at 1376–77 (“[T]he President directed all agencies to make deregulatory policy shifts, but without regard to the net benefits, legislative edicts, and societal conditions that led to the earlier regulatory actions.”).

        [54].      Joel A. Mintz, The President’s “Two for One” Executive Order and the Interpretation Mandate of the National Environmental Policy Act: A Legal Constraint on Presidential Power, 87 UMKC L. Rev. 681, 693 (2019).

        [55].      E.g., Exec. Order No. 13,948, 85 Fed. Reg. 59,649 (Sept. 23, 2020) (ordering the Secretary of Health and Human Services to adjust prescription drug prices under Medicare).

        [56].      Exec. Order No. 13,778, 82 Fed. Reg. 12,497 (Feb. 28, 2017).

        [57].      Id. § 3, see also Buzbee, supra note 19, at 1383; Michael A. Livermore & Richard L. Revesz, Regulatory Review, Capture, and Agency Inaction, 101 Geo. L.J. 1337 (2013).

        [58].      Buzbee, supra note 19, at 1383.

        [59].      Seidenfeld, supra note 25, at 1453 (arguing that if the President makes their view known before the agency has deliberated, the agency is likely to be biased towards the President’s desired outcome). Manheim and Watts divide presidential orders into those that are “legally binding” (that is those “that carry the force and effect of law”) and those that are not legally binding (that is those that “do not themselves alter legal rights or obligations”). Manheim & Watts, supra note 29, at 1764–65. Orders that regulate private parties directly fall into the former category. Id. That distinction, however, is difficult to draw and not effective, because everything the President does is “binding” in some sense. Indeed, Manheim and Watts recognize that their categories “blur together around the margins,” and non-binding orders have a significant effect, “even if the effect is largely political instead of legal.” Id. at 1766.

        [60].      Intention to Review and Rescind or Revise the Clean Water Rule, 82 Fed. Reg. 12,532, 12,532 (Mar. 6, 2017); see also Buzbee, supra note 19, at 1383.

        [61].      See Jeremy P. Jacobs and Pamela King, Trump’s Rewrite Is Finalized. What Happens Now?, E & E News (Apr. 21, 2020), https://www.eenews.net/stories/1062934329 [https://perma.cc/7T6Y-9MU
M]; Amena H. Saiyid, Lawyers See Maui Opinion as Grounds to Challenge Trump Water Rule, Bloomberg Law (Apr. 27, 2020, 7:37 AM) https://news.bloomberglaw.com/environment-and-energy/
lawyers-see-maui-opinion-as-grounds-to-challenge-trump-water-rule [https://perma.cc/5V7E-59C4].

        [62].      The APA sometimes uses the term “agency” to refer to the officer who heads the agency. See, e.g., 5 U.S.C. § 557(b); see also Michael Asimow, When the Curtain Falls: Separation of Functions in the Federal Administrative Agencies, 81 Colum. L. Rev. 759, 766 (1981) (referring to 5 U.S.C. § 554(d)(C).

        [63].      Kovacs, supra note 5, at 65.

        [64].      5 U.S.C. § 553.

        [65].      Manheim & Watts, supra note 29, at 1759; Stack, supra note 4, at 552, 554–55.

        [66].      5 U.S.C. § 706(2)(A); Kovacs, supra note 12, at 550.

        [67].      Franklin v. Massachusetts, 505 U.S. 788, 800–01 (1992).

        [68].      Kovacs,  supra note 5, at 103. Plaintiffs, of course, may wait for the agency to implement the President’s directive and sue the agency. See Franklin, 505 U.S. at 828 (Scalia, J., concurring in part and concurring in the judgment). That approach, however, is inadequate. The agency must follow the President’s instructions; its lack of discretion makes its action unreviewable. Cf. Dep’t of Transp. v. Pub. Citizen, 541 U.S. 752 (2004) (holding that where a presidential order deprives an agency of discretion, the agency need not analyze the environmental effects of its action). Moreover, the agency cannot explain the President’s reasoning, but can only supply a post hoc rationale for an already-final decision. Kovacs, supra note 5, at 112.

        [69].      See Ruhl & Salzman, supra note 28, at 1741; Elizabeth Landers, White House: Trump’s Tweets Are ‘Official Statements,’ CNN (June 6, 2017, 4:37 PM), http://www.cnn.com/2017/06/06/politics/trump

-tweets-official-statements/index.html [https://perma.cc/DXM6-X9GC]; Executive Power—Presidential Directives—In Tweets, President Purports to Ban Transgender Servicemembers, 131 Harv. L. Rev. 934, 937–38 (2018) (“[T]he basic principles governing presidential instruments…tell us that authoritative presidential directives, whatever their form, are legally binding on subordinates.”).

        [70].      Gen. Elec. Co. v. EPA, 290 F.3d 377, 382 (D.C. Cir. 2002) (stating that a rule is legislative if it “binds private parties or the agency itself with the ‘force of law’”); Cass R. Sunstein, Chevron Step Zero, 92 Va. L. Rev. 187, 222 (2006) (“[A] decision has the ‘force of law’ if the agency is legally bound by it.” (citing FEC v. Nat’l Rifle Ass’n, 254 F.3d 173, 185–86 (D.C. Cir. 2001))); cf. Elec. Privacy Info. Ctr. v. Internal Revenue Serv., 910 F.3d 1232, 1244 (D.C. Cir. 2018) (“[A]n agency can create a non-discretionary duty by binding itself through a regulation carrying the force of law.”).

        [71].      Stack, supra note 4, at 597 (“[J]udicial enforceability is not necessary to the existence of a norm having the status of law.”).

        [72].      See, e.g. Memorandum of Law in Support of Motion for Summary Judgment at 15, Knight First Amendment Inst. at Columbia Univ. v. Donald J. Trump, No. 1:17-cv-05205-NRB (S.D.N.Y. Oct. 13, 2017), https://static.reuters.com/resources/media/editorial/20171016/knightvtrump–DOJSJmotion.p
df [https://perma.cc/K84L-MF83]; Defendant’s Supplemental Submission & Further Response to Plaintiff’s Post-Briefing Notices at 2, 4, James Madison Project v. Dep’t of Justice, No. 1:17-cv-00144-APM (D.D.C. Nov. 13, 2017), https://assets.documentcloud.org/documents/4200037/Trump-Twitter-20
171113.pdf [https://perma.cc/3K6Y-D84W].

        [73].      See Adam Aton, Trump Tweet Becomes Policy After Firefighters Rebuffed It, E&E News (Aug. 9, 2018), https://www.eenews.net/stories/1060093713 [https://perma.cc/T2K6-6BWC];, U.S. Secretary of Commerce Wilbur Ross Issues Directive for National Marine Fisheries Service to Facilitate Water Access in California Wildfire Relief Efforts, U.S. Dep’t of Com. (Aug. 8, 2018), https://www.com
merce.gov/news/press-releases/2018/08/us-secretary-commerce-wilbur-ross-issues-directive-national-m
arine [https://perma.cc/93TD-Y3CH]; cf. Shawn Snow & Leo Shane III, Trump Says Tweet Serves as ‘Notification’ to Congress that US May ‘Quickly & Fully Strike Back’ Against Iran, Military Times (Jan. 5, 2020), https://www.militarytimes.com/flashpoints/2020/01/05/trump-says-tweet-serves-as-notif
ication-to-congress-that-us-may-quickly-fully-strike-back-against-iran/ [https://perma.cc/N43M-T2EG]. But see Matthew Chou, Agency Interpretations of Executive Orders, 71 Admin. L. Rev. 555, 582 (2019) (“[T]he military declined to act on President Trump’s July 26, 2017 tweets that purported to exclude transgender individuals from the military, until the President issued a presidential memorandum.”).

        [74].      Hawaii v. Trump, 859 F.3d 741, 773 n.14 (9th Cir. 2017) (citing a tweet when noting that “the President recently confirmed his assessment that it is the ‘countries’ that are inherently dangerous, rather than the 180 million individual nationals of those countries who are barred from entry under the President’s ‘travel ban’ ”) (citing Donald J. Trump (@realDonaldTrump), Twitter (June 5, 2017, 6:20 PM), https://twitter.com/realDonaldTrump/status/871899511525961728), judgment vacated, 138 S. Ct. 377 (2017) (mem.), vacated, 874 F.3d 1112 (9th Cir. 2017).

        [75].      See supra text accompanying notes 22–24.

        [76].      Prakash, supra note 23, at 992.

        [77].      See, e.g., Shane, supra note 23; Martin S. Flaherty, The Most Dangerous Branch, 105 Yale L.J. 1725 (1996); A. Michael Froomkin, The Imperial Presidency’s New Vestments, 88 Nw. U. L. Rev. 1346 (1994); Heidi Kitrosser, The Accountable Executive, 93 Minn. L. Rev. 1741 (2009); Percival, Presidential Management, supra note 19; Peter M. Shane, Independent Policymaking and Presidential Power: A Constitutional Analysis, 57 Geo. Wash. L. Rev. 596 (1989); Jed Handelsman Shugerman, The Indecisions of 1789: Strategic Ambiguity and the Imaginary Unitary Executive (Part I) (Fordham Law Legal Studies Research Paper No. 3596566, June 23, 2020), https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?
abstract_id=3596566 [https://perma.cc/6URZ-S46L].

        [78].      M. Elizabeth Magill, The Real Separation in Separation of Powers Law, 86 Va. L. Rev. 1127, 1130 (2000); see also id. at 1131, 1159.

        [79].      The Federalist No. 51, at 289–90 (James Madison) (Clinton Rossiter ed., 1999).

        [80].      Magill, supra note 78, at 1194–97.

        [81].      Id. at 1175.

        [82].      See id. at 1196; see also Michael J. Teter, Congressional Gridlock’s Threat to Separation of Powers, 2013 Wis. L. Rev. 1097, 1135 (“[N]o matter the approach one chooses to follow, the core elements of separation of powers remain: separated branches performing certain functions while serving as checks on the others as a means of preserving the proper balance of power.”). But see Eric A. Posner, Balance-of-Powers Arguments, the Structural Constitution, and the Problem of Executive “Underenforcement,” 164 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1677, 1682 (2016) (suggesting that the balance of powers “metaphor is not useful”).

        [83].      See Watts, supra note 11, at 724–25 (“[W]e justify the existence and the legitimacy of what would otherwise be a ‘headless fourth branch’ by the fact that the political branches can and do exert control over agency heads.”); cf. Lisa Schultz Bressman, Procedures as Politics in Administrative Law, 108 Colum. L. Rev. Sidebar 1 (2008) (“The Court therefore sees its role as attempting to reconcile the needs of both political branches for control of agency policy. It establishes the conditions for conflict and compromise between the political branches to produce politically reasonable policy outcomes. These conditions are inherent in separation of powers.”).

        [84].      Kovacs, supra note 5, at 89.

        [85].      Michael Ray Harris, Standing in the Way of Judicial Review: Assertion of the Deliberative Process Privilege in APA Cases, 53 St. Louis U. L.J. 349, 380–81 (2009).

        [86].      Franklin v. Massachusetts, 505 U.S. 788, 800–01 (1992).

        [87].      See Kovacs, supra note 5, at 78.

        [88].      Id. at 90. Manheim and Watts pointed out that “separation-of-powers principles” cut “in the direction of protecting the president” and “in the direction of checking the president.” Manheim & Watts, supra note 29, at 1810 (emphasis in original). That is particularly so because recent decades have “seen a massive transfer of policymaking authority from the legislative branch to the executive branch, coupled with increasingly aggressive attempts by Presidents to control that policymaking.” Id.

        [89].      See Strauss, supra note 19, at 754 (observing that when Congress delegates rulemaking authority, it intends for that authority to “be exercised at some remove from raw politics, pursuant to the APA and subject to FOIA”).

        [90].      The President & Accounting Offices, 1 Op. Att’y Gen. 624, 625–26 (1823).

        [91].      See Kevin M. Stack, The President’s Statutory Powers to Administer the Laws, 106 Colum. L. Rev. 263, 318 (2006) (“[S]tatutory constructions that imply directive powers disrupt Congress’s interest in specifying the procedures through which statutory delegations should be implemented.”).

        [92].      Valerie C. Brannon, Cong. Research Serv., LSB10172, Can a President Amend Regulations by Executive Order? 2 (2018); see also Seidenfeld, supra note 19, at 1786 (“[I]f Congress can withhold the power from the president entirely, it seems logical that Congress should be able to condition the exercise of that power however it sees fit.”).

        [93].      Seidenfeld, supra note 19, at 1787.

        [94].      See Harold J. Krent, From a Unitary to a Unilateral Presidency, 88 B.U. L. Rev. 523, 550–51 (2008); see also Christopher J. Walker, Restoring Congress’s Role in the Modern Administrative State, 116 Mich. L. Rev. 1101, 1115 (2018) (emphasizing Congress’s lawmaking power as a means of retaining balance of powers).

        [95].      Kendall v. United States ex rel. Stokes, 37 U.S. 524, 613 (1838).

        [96].      Thomas W. Merrill, Presidential Administration and the Traditions of Administrative Law, 115 Colum. L. Rev. 1953, 1980 (2015); see also Krent, supra note 94, at 550–51, 558; cf. Percival, Presidential Management, supra note 19, at 1005 (arguing that it undermines the value of the Senate’s advice and consent if the President can override an officer’s decision in any event).

        [97].      See Morrison v. Olson, 487 U.S. 654, 709 (1988) (Scalia, J., dissenting) (asserting that all “of the purely executive powers of government must be within the full control of the President”).

        [98].      Even if the Constitution requires all executive power to be lodged in the President, “a constitutional requirement of course does not imply that the legislation complies with it.” Stack, supra note 91, at 274.

        [99].      Richard W. Murphy, The DIY Unitary Executive, 63 Ariz. L. Rev. (forthcoming 2020) (manuscript at 35) (on file with author).

     [100].      U.S. Const. art. I, § 8, cl. 18; see also Seila Law LLC v. Consumer Fin. Prot. Bureau, 140 S. Ct. 2183, 2226 (Kagan, J., concurring in the judgment with respect to severability and dissenting in part) (stating that Congress has the power “to structure administrative institutions as the times demand, so long as the President retains the ability to carry out his constitutional duties”).

     [101].      Seila Law LLC, 140 S. Ct. at 2227.

     [102].      Percival, Presidential Management, supra note 19, at 999.

     [103].      Id. at 1008 (“If the president has express authority to overturn the legal consequences of agency decisions in some circumstances, but not others, the argument for inferring congressional intent to permit the president generally to displace agency decisions is somewhat weaker.”); see also Stack, supra note 91, at 227–228.

     [104].      Andrew Kent, Ethan J. Leib & Jed Handelsman Shugerman, Faithful Execution and Article II, 132 Harv. L. Rev. 2111, 2186 (2019).

     [105].      Id. at 2192.

     [106].      Buzbee, supra note 19, at 1390–91; see also Strauss, supra note 19, at 711 (“The important propositions are that Congress (validly) assigned decision here and specified that decision should be taken by this official, following these procedures, within these legal constraints.”); id. at 759 (“Congress’s arrangements of government are a part of the law that the President is to assure will ‘be faithfully executed.’”).

     [107].      See Murphy, supra note 99 (“The executive power to implement the laws does not carry with it the power to violate them (which would, in any event, violate the president’s duties under the Take Care Clause).”).

     [108].      Kovacs, supra note 5.

     [109].      Id. at 82–88.

     [110].      Id. at 88–95.

     [111].      Id. at 97–114.

     [112].      Id. at 114–19.

     [113].      Id. at 64 n.8.

     [114].      5 U.S.C. § 553(b)–(c). As Manheim and Watts observed, a court may consider an order “binding” “[i]f a President or his subordinates treat a presidential order as binding—or if litigants otherwise can demonstrate that an order is binding as a practical matter.” Manheim & Watts, supra note 29, at 1805.

     [115].      5 U.S.C. § 553(c) (“[T]he agency shall incorporate in the rules adopted a concise general statement of their basis and purpose.”).

     [116].      Kovacs, supra note 5, at 103–04.

     [117].      5 U.S.C. § 706(2)(A).

     [118].      See Kovacs, supra note 5, at 97.

     [119].      Id. at 100–01

     [120].      Id. at 98–99, 104–05. Peter Shane explained how presidential usurpation of agency discretion reduces transparency and democratic dialogue and increases the risk that decisions will be “based solely on passion or ‘interest’” rather than the concerns that animated the statute. Shane, supra note 23, at 160, 163, 164, 183; see also Percival, Presidential Management, supra note 19, 1010 (“[T]here is reason to suspect that the White House would be more inclined to intervene to achieve short-term political gains than to promote the objectives of regulatory statutes Congress has entrusted agencies to administer.”).

     [121].      See Lawrence Solum, Legal Theory Lexicon: Second Best & Nonideal Theory, Legal Theory Blog (Sept. 14, 2014, 7:38 PM), http://lsolum.typepad.com/legaltheory/2014/09/legal-theory-lexicon-se
cond-best-nonideal-theory.html [https://perma.cc/69ZR-NLF8].

     [122].      Id. (“[W]hen the first-best policy option is unavailable, then normative legal theorists should consider second-best solutions.”).

     [123].      Cf. Gillian E. Metzger, Ordinary Administrative Law as Constitutional Common Law, 110 Colum. L. Rev. 479, 485 (2010) (“[S]eeking to enforce constitutional norms through ordinary administrative law better accords with constitutional principles, and may be less intrusive on the policymaking prerogatives of the political branches, than efforts to segregate out [administrative law and constitutional common law].”); id. at 489 (explaining that administrative law requirements can avoid constitutional violations and enable courts to avoid addressing constitutional issues); David Zaring, Toward Separation of Powers Realism, 37 Yale J. Reg. 708, 749 (2020) (arguing that separation of powers claims fail to achieve their remedial goals because the APA provides a “less intrusive alternative”).

     [124].      See Stack, supra note 4, at 543.

     [125].      Id. at 590 (distinguishing the transparency of the Statutory President’s orders from the President’s influence on officers).

     [126].      See Manheim & Watts, supra note 29, at 1764–65; Watts, supra note 11, at 688–705; see also, e.g., Juliet Eilperin & Josh Dawsey, Trump Pushes to Allow New Logging in Alaska’s Tongass National Forest, Wash. Post (Aug. 27, 2019, 2:29 PM), https://www.washingtonpost.com/climate-environment/
trump-pushes-to-allow-new-logging-in-alaskas-tongass-national-forest/2019/08/27/b4ca78d6-c832-11e
9-be05-f76ac4ec618c_story.html? [https://perma.cc/J33C-ZSS8].

     [127].      Cf. Watts, supra note 11, at 725 (“[E]xpertise forcing threatens to drive political influences underground where such influences will be protected from public scrutiny, accountability, and oversight.”). Watts suggests compelling agencies to disclose presidential influence, but necessarily couples that with the incentive of more favorable standards of judicial review. Id. at 735. Absent the “carrot,” the “stick” would “drive political influences underground.” Id. at 725, 735.

     [128].      Cf. id.; Stack, supra note 4, at 590 (“[W]hen the President merely urges administrators to pursue a course of action . . . transparency is lacking.”).

     [129].      Watts does not go so far as to suggest this. Watts, supra note 11, at 735 (suggesting that agencies should be required “to disclose the substance of significant executive supervision” (emphasis added)); see also id. at 743.

     [130].      Underground influence does not eliminate agency control, undermine the legislative bargains underlying statutory delegations, or fail to execute the law faithfully. See supra Part II.

     [131].      See Metzger, supra note 123, at 491, 492, 530.

     [132].      See Kovacs, supra note 5, at 98–99, 104–05.

     [133].      Id. at 104–05.

     [134].      5 U.S.C. § 706(2)(A).

     [135].      See Kovacs, supra note 5, at 78–82, 109–111.

     [136].      For scholarly opposition to that theory, see supra note 77.

     [137].      Cf. Kovacs, supra note 12, at 561–65 (analyzing the problems with unilateral presidential action).

     [138].      Cf. Yoo, supra note 26, at 243 (“[D]ebates over the unitary executive are not merely a matter of partisanship, as some have claimed, but rather raise fundamental issues about the proper balance of power within the federal government that transcend the politics of the moment.”).

2021 Federal Clerkships: Can Order Emerge From Chaos?

Postscript | Administrative Law
2021 Federal Clerkships: Can Order Emerge From Chaos?
by Carl Tobias*

Vol. 94, Postscript (June 2020)
94 S. Cal. L. Rev. Postscript 1 (2020)

Keywords: Federal Clerkship, Federal Law Clerkship Hiring Plan 

2021 FEDERAL clerkships: CAN ORDER EMERGE FROM CHAOS?

Carl Tobias[*]

This is a perfect juncture for analyzing 2021 federal judicial clerkships. Many aspirants recently finished half of their legal education. Six appeals courts’ members have agreed to honor a new Federal Law Clerk Hiring Plan (hereinafter referred to as “the pilot”) that is currently in its second year. The pilot directly proscribes seeking and permitting clerkship applications and recommendation letters until June 15, 2020 and prohibits student clerkship interviews and judicial offers before June 16, 2020.[1] However, certain judges within these six tribunals will not respect the pilot during its second year, even though jurists in the seven remaining courts of appeals might follow the new plan. The Administrative Office of the United States Courts (“AO”) extended 2L students OSCAR access in February while suspending in January 2014 the 2003 clerk hiring plan—whereby 3L employment began near Labor Day—and judges will soon consider aspirants. Clues offered below may assist prospects in securing the coveted positions which start in 2021.

 

I.  Federal Appellate Clerkships

Most of the 270 appeals court jurists have filled posts, yet a significant number remain open. Many hired before the set period prescribed by the pilot, which other judges honored.[2] There are many phenomena that can explain the variation in hiring by federal appellate court judges, including the nascent pilot program, the 2014 AO discontinuation of an earlier hiring plan, and the reactions of numerous judges to a U.S. Court of Appeals for the District of Columbia Circuit announcement in January 2013. Seven years ago, the D.C. Circuit, America’s second most important court, which had assiduously followed the 2003 clerkship hiring rules for years, announced that the tribunal’s jurists, who found the once-workable plan had not been efficacious, would grant offers whenever they wanted.[3] The statement quickly precipitated a hiring frenzy that has continued since and promotes greater uncertainty this season, which the pilot’s implementation compounds.[4]

Those developments suggest that applicants who hope to clerk for judges rejecting the plan and even students who might wish to capture positions on the D.C., First, Second, Third, Seventh and Ninth Circuits, which abide by the pilot, should move immediately. Clerkships for all jurists who dutifully comply with the plan are extremely competitive. They serve on courts of last resort which decide exceptional issues, encompassing abortion, civil rights, discrimination and immigration, or are ensconced in particularly desirable venues, including New York, Chicago and San Francisco, which means that numerous appellate court judges may favor aspirants who bring recent district clerkship or legal practice experience. Nonetheless, even on those appeals courts, some members in less popular areas recruit later. For example, frigid Vermont, Wisconsin or Idaho winters and steamy District of Columbia, Philadelphia or Phoenix summers can discourage numbers of potential applicants. When carefully scrutinizing the employment possibilities, students might want to remember that they will actually clerk for only a year.

Additional jurists, whose clerkship posts are not so distinguished or whose chambers are clearly in locales that applicants would prefer considerably less, have yet to employ students. They include portions of the Fifth, Eighth and Tenth Circuits but also in the Fourth, Sixth and Eleventh Circuits.[5] Finally, certain judges may be respecting the nascent pilot or awaiting two years of grades. Therefore, a number may have slots available,[6] yet time is certainly of the essence.

 

II.  Federal Clerkships History

The D.C. Circuit ignited a firestorm which consumed hiring by most of the 1,100 district court jurists in 2013 and continued raging subsequently. After the D.C. Circuit’s announcement, numerous judges picked 2Ls, but others acted slowly, perhaps favoring the clerkship system that performed well over the decade after 2003. This endeavor relied on Labor Day for the benchmark when 3L students could proffer, and jurists could receive, submissions; judges were concomitantly to delay arranging interviews until a week later when they might have extended offers.[7]

Problems complicate identification of exactly what happened after the D.C. Circuit jettisoned the standard regime.[8] Aspirants were not certain about how to pursue clerkships and were discharging time-consuming law review duties. Many jurists offered no or limited guidance. Schools were unclear regarding how to advise candidates. They lacked material on judges and closely observed National Association for Law Placement (NALP) guidelines, which cautiously approached the D.C. Circuit decision. However, by April 2013, in a seeming effort to resuscitate the collapsing plan, the AO imposed June 28 as the date when rising 3Ls commenced applying.[9]

In 2013, employment did vary considerably. Most jurists slowly responded to the D.C. Circuit’s notice, but in time more abandoned the decade-old process, which the AO had elaborated. They found that the scheme permitted inefficiency, “exploding offers,” cheating, and secrecy.[10] A number complied with the 2003 and recent measures or decided to hire later for numerous reasons. Many chief judges, who administer district courts, respected the practices, as they deemed the notions constructive and probably wished to serve as role models. Specific jurists could have perceived that the nuanced strictures operated impressively or were awaiting the AO determination to end or refine the 2003 clerkship plan. Some judges may have preferred the late summer deadlines, recognized that numbers of aspirants can be accomplished clerks or thought the frenetic procedures were absurd or undignified.

Instructive empirical data in responses to a 2013 NALP member survey detected that judges’ hiring endeavors provoked “real concerns about [OSCAR’s] diminished utility” for clearly notifying students and their presenting clerkship submissions.[11] Jurists correspondingly “looked beyond OSCAR” to provide salient information, which prompted surging “email and paper applications,” while confusion in OSCAR materials’ reliability, notably the timing of applications, dissuaded manifold students from participating.[12] Legal educators in turn consistently “favored opening OSCAR” sooner and uncoupling clerkship applications from the hiring plan deadlines.[13] The AO carefully effectuated these recommendations in Fall 2013[14] and clarified hiring over the next several years by discontinuing the regime a few months later.[15]

 

III.  More Recent Guidance

In 2014, Administrative Office Director Judge John Bates remarked to jurists that the plan was ending and “no further dates [were] being set” for clerkships,[16] while the AO adopted voluntary “Best Practices to support transparency,” requesting that NALP craft those procedures “from the law school perspective.”[17] He implored judges to use the online mechanism.[18] The notice, which granted 1Ls access, meant that jurists sent OSCAR copious additional positions.[19] Discontinuation concomitantly seemed to propel hiring, witnessed by the surfeit of accelerated listings the past six years.[20] Nevertheless, relatively few judges employed clerks ahead of January, perhaps waiting on third semester grades, the 2014 AO plan change, or subsequent guidance.

In February 2018, the AO announced a pilot that would govern 2020–21 clerkship hiring.[21] This initiative deserves considerable review because some courts and jurists followed the plan last year or will this season. Thus, evaluation might aid their coordination and people who hope to begin clerking in August 2021. The chief judges of the D.C., Second, Seventh and Ninth Circuits and deans who lead prominent law schools proposed the regulatory system that would ostensibly expand student participation, while certain jurists on these tribunals, the First and Third Circuits and the Districts of Connecticut, District of Columbia and Massachusetts subscribed to the pilot.[22] The AO chose February 2020 OSCAR access for members of the 2021 class, who submit applications in June, permitted judges to extend, and students correspondingly to accept, clerkship offers basically upon receipt and in turn prohibited exploding offers.[23]

Several law professors who track court of appeals law clerk employment detect that some jurists honor the plan but numerous other judges whose courts subscribe to, or do not follow the pilot, eschew it. However, the writers find very difficult ascertaining exactly what is happening, while strong pressure to satisfy the pilot requirements exacerbates transparency’s dearth.[24] The faculty members state that this paucity concomitantly helps students plus schools with access to inside information, and the plan can allow judges to select clerks early, issue exploding offers, and hire practitioners.[25] The scholars register concern that numbers of particular jurists who follow and support the pilot constitute appointees of Democratic presidents whose chambers are situated on the coastlines whom more progressive aspirants could favor, and numerous judges who seem to eschew while opposing the plan comprise appointees of Republican presidents whose chambers are located throughout the heartland whom conservative students prefer.[26]

In short, plentiful factors leave this season uncertain. [27] Essential is how many jurists now adopt the pilot. Others may be the limited, clear data on what happened subsequent to 2013. Related were June 1L OSCAR access, the 2003 plan suspension, the Best Practices’ creation and circulation, the number of judgessaliently those eschewing OSCAR deploymentwho learned about the procedures, and how completely jurists adhere to the guidelines furnished.

 

IV.  Federal District Clerkships Reprised

Candidates should meticulously apply the concepts assessed by consulting the AO views, judges’ OSCAR postings, and court websites. To jumpstart the search, I provide a representative sample of how numerous district jurists and courts proceeded after January 2013 from which students can extrapolate. Potential applicants might remember that, while district court judges and tribunals traditionally recruit later, the 2014 discontinuation of the 2003 plan, the institution of several Best Practices, and the uncertainty about how careful and systemic pilot compliance will be acutely show that confusion and variability could plague this year.[28]

Some judges acted earlier to pick clerks in the last few seasons. Phenomena, which encompass prestige, location, and competitiveness, indicate aspirants can rely on heavily and sparsely populated districts when they set 2021 priorities. This approach reveals that numbers of jurists did conclude 2L employment by May in Arizona, Colorado, Northern Ohio, Maryland, Northern Georgia, Eastern Missouri, and Northern Texas.[29] However, the courts include so many judges that all districts and jurists require verification.[30] A plethora completed hiring on June 28 (for 3Ls) in 2013 and earlier (for 2Ls) subsequently until 2019. Illuminating were Eastern Virginia jurists, who promptly collected applications, conducted interviews, and chose before March.

Since 2013, numerous judges had yet to fill positions by April, while specific ones might have not even begun. Montana jurists, who principally notify students during the year when they will clerk, are illustrative. Eastern California, and Middle Pennsylvania, which regularly start later had plenty of fall slots, and districts in rural venues, like Wyoming, also experienced vacancies then. Finally, plentiful judges supplied negligible information, but a few courts enhanced transparency by placing strictures prominently on websites.[31]

 

V.  gathering Additional Information

Applicants could depend on these snapshots of the past six years and how this season commenced. Persons may also consult the information which numbers of jurists efficiently list through OSCAR and websites that they or courts maintain, yet some jurists use neither. A related way that people solicit profitable material is phoning and emailing chambers to seek advice from law clerks or judicial assistants, namely for jurists who ignore OSCAR or employ it but disregard the rules enunciated. These inquiries elicit much data respecting hiring processes: notably who screens candidates and crucial timeframes which govern submissions, interviews, and clerkship offers.

 

VI.  Additional Clerkships

As myriad persistent students frantically pursue clerkships at the thirteen appellate courts and ninety-four district courts, committed aspirants might wish to seriously contemplate numerous possibilities serving with additional particular courts and copious judges whom applicants may have overlooked or not considered. They run along a gamut of appeals courts, district courts, and Article I tribunals. Senior appellate court and trial level jurists constitute preeminent examples.[32] Another is chief judges, who upon ascension secure one more clerk.[33] A related promising source would be President Donald Trump’s nominees and confirmees; the chief executive must fill seventy-two positions which currently remain unoccupied, and competition might be less stiff for those posts because smaller numbers of students meticulously track the vacancies.[34]

 

VII.  Early Preparation

Aspirants ought to plan early. For instance, when 1L examinations conclude, students should actively participate in law review competitions to ensure their selection. Once designated, picks need to be rigorously involved, as jurists value membership, specifically on the editorial board, which perceptibly demonstrates commitment to robust intellectual activity. Students can diligently prepare to apply for clerkships by assembling a comprehensive list of judges, signing up for OSCAR, and creating a profile. Aspirants could solicit advice on jurists whom they can target from knowledgeable professors or 3L colleagues while seeking powerful faculty letters of recommendation.

 

VIII.  Applications

Judges directly receive clerkship applications from plentiful students, who ought to consider the starting period the deadline, as numerous jurists hire on a rolling basis. Candidates should astutely choose because OSCAR’s maximum number of applications has been 100,[35] (although deficient transparency confounds this). Aspirants who employ paper submissions need to carefully place materials in a single envelope which promotes tracking by judicial chambers. The large number of applications indicates that cover letters and resumes must be short. Cover letters ought to persuasively explain why aspirants do have substantial competence and how collegially applicants would perform in chambers. Students normally advance three recommendation letters, two of which faculty craft and one that a practitioner develops. The writing sample must be concise enough that it deftly provokes reading, yet sufficiently long to display fine analytical, critical research, and exquisite drafting, capability.

 

IX.  Interviews

Numerous interviews actually resemble law firm “call-backs,” even though aspects can be peculiar to the bench and individual jurists.[36] Court members seemingly have different perspectives, expectations, interests, and requirements. Substantial numbers of judges clearly are intelligent, diligent, ethical, and independent, while most have balanced temperament. Candidates need to learn all possible regarding specific judges’ diverse backgrounds: colleges attended, career history, and conditions of appointment.[37] Prospects must correspondingly examine jurists’ writing, namely decisions.

Aspirants should concomitantly anticipate lines of inquiry that bench members, law clerks, and additional court personnel will scrutinize by, for example, contacting present and former clerks. Interviews’ salient purposes are cogently ascertaining whether candidates have effectively acquired the necessary competence and can collaboratively interact with others. Applicants must be especially solicitous of chamber personnel, as court staff need to perform smoothly on a team and judges prize their opinions. The queries, thus, could address a broad spectrum from recent judicial treatment of discrete areas, notably criminal procedure, reproductive freedom, or employment discrimination, to favorite Supreme Court Justices, hobbies or wines.

Some jurists eschew making final determinations at interviews because they conscientiously prefer to interview every individual and select clerks who appear extremely capable and can be rigorous teammates of the permanent staff.[38] Increasing numbers extend offers during interviews or at their conclusion, which means aspirants need to realistically prepare for this eventuality.

X.  Offers

Judges may variously notify students when tendering offers, but certain dimensions of the process seem analogous to procedures that law reviews use in choosing manuscripts. Numerous jurists expect instant acceptances, a concept which distinctly resembles journals’ “short fuse” or exploding offers.[39] Judges might withdraw any offers that prospective clerks fail to swiftly accept in phone conversations when they are delivered, which writers trenchantly characterize as “disappearing offers,” even though the nascent pilot bars this measure.[40]

Jurists could accord students one week for making clerkship determinations. Applicants with the intestinal fortitude can attempt to leverage the opportunities for circumstances which they perceive as superior.[41] Certain judges apparently encouraged applicants to leverage offers by requesting that aspirants directly inform chambers upon offers’ extension.[42] The Administrative Office Best Practices also urge jurists to supply complete instructions on employment processes and grant students reasonable time for cautiously weighing offers but do not proscribe speedy acceptances.[43] However, the pilot insists that students have forty-eight hours to reach this decision.[44]

 

Conclusion

I hope that these clues for attaining clerkships prove helpful. Bon voyage.

 


[*] *.              Williams Chair in Law, University of Richmond School of Law. This piece is for David Lat whose perceptive insights on federal law clerk employment and so much else in law and life inspire all people who know his work and David. I wish to thank Margaret Sanner for valuable suggestions, Jamie Wood, Jane Baber and Emily Benedict for valuable research and careful editing, the University of Richmond Law Library staff for valuable research, the Southern California Law Review Postscript editors for excellent editing and sound advice, Ashley Griffin Hudak and Leslee Stone for excellent processing as well as Russell Williams and the Hunton Andrews Kurth Summer Research Endowment Fund for generous, continuing support. Numerous federal appellate and district court judges, law clerks and additional court personnel, law professors, Career Development Office (CDO) professionals and law students afforded many ideas examined below. Remaining errors are mine alone.

 [1]. Admin. Office of the U.S. Courts, Federal Law Clerk Hiring Plan (2018) [hereinafter Hiring Plan]; Admin. Office of the U.S. Courts, Federal Law Clerk Hiring Plan 2nd Pilot Year (2019) [hereinafter 2nd Pilot Year],  https://oscar.courts.gov/federal_law_clerk_hiring_pilot; see also Will Baude, A Proposal for a New Clerkship Hiring Plan (When The Current One Collapses), Reason: Volokh Conspiracy (Feb. 10, 2020, 3:55 PM), https://reason.com/2020/02/10/a-proposal-for-a-new-federal-clerkship-hiring-plan-when-the-current-one-collapses [https://perma.cc/8KYL-6VVN] (analyzing the 2019 federal law clerk employment pilot and suggesting a new plan).

 [2]. See Edward Becker et al., The Federal Judicial Law Clerk Hiring Problem and the Modest March 1 Solution, 104 Yale L. J. 207, 215–16 (1994); Alex Kozinski, Confessions of a Bad Apple, 100 Yale L. J. 1707, 1725 (1991).

 [3]. See also Carl Tobias, Tips for Capturing 2014 Federal Court Clerkships, 66 Vand. L. Rev. En Banc 145, 146 n.2 (2013); David Lat, The Law Clerk Hiring Plan: Really, Really Dead Now, Above the Law (Jan. 30, 2013, 12:38 PM), https://abovethelaw.com/2013/01/the-law-clerk-hiring-plan-really-really-dead-now [https://perma.cc/KRX4-ANKQ]. It is unclear why so many federal judges have defected from the nascent pilot and every prior iteration of the Federal Law Clerk Hiring Plan. See Kozinski, supra note 2. See generally Louis F. Oberdorfer & Michael N. Levy, Response, On Clerkship Selection: A Reply to the Bad Apple, 101 Yale L. J. 1097, 1108 (1992) (addressing the “inefficient, expensive, disruptive, and demeaning” way that federal judges have selected their law clerks and proffering suggestions for improvement).

 [4]. Karen Sloan, Law Deans Implore Federal Judges to Follow Clerk Hiring Plan, Law.com, (Jan. 29, 2020, 2:11 PM) https://www.law.com/2020/01/29/law-deans-implore-federal-judges-to-follow-law-clerk-hiring-plan [https://perma.cc/X8J9-5FF4]. The pilot ostensibly attempts to remedy or ameliorate what many observers contend has become a two-track process. Letter from Kerry Abrams et al. to the Members of the Federal Judiciary (Jan. 22, 2020), https://images.law.com/contrib/content/uploads/docum
ents/292/60749/Deans-Letter-to-the-Federal-Judiciary-January-20201.pdf [https://perma.cc/BRT7-E52
W].

 [5]. Aspirants should consider applying to positions in Jackson, Fargo, Casper, Greenville, Akron or Montgomery. See Jack Goldsmith (@jacklgoldsmith), Twitter (Feb. 10, 2020, 11:51 AM), https://twit
ter.com/jacklgoldsmith/status/1226955076738007040 [https://perma.cc/KJP3-CRVN] (urging students to apply beyond “so-called elite federal circuits”).

 [6]. Indeed, 2020 OSCAR postings include 2021 court of appeals clerkships. See, e.g., Weekly Update: New Positions Posted (March 9 – March 16, 2020), OSCAR Blog (Mar. 16, 2020), https://oscar.uscourts.gov/blog_post/_1/348/Weekly_Update_New_Positions_Posted_March_9_-_Marc
h_16_2020 [https://perma.cc/M7XA-2EGN]; Weekly Update: New Positions Posted (March 30 – April 6, 2020), OSCAR Blog (Apr. 6, 2020), https://oscar.uscourts.gov/blog_post/_1/354/Weekly_Update_Ne
w_Positions_Posted_March_30_-_April_6_2020 [https://perma.cc/32AD-VSVV].

 [7]. Carl Tobias, Salvaging the 2013 Federal Law Clerk Hiring Season, 91 Wash. U. L. Rev. 243, 244 (2013).

 [8]. Considerable empirical data and other relevant information are private or anecdotal and complex variations existed among schools, courts, judges, and students. However, I can posit a snapshot by consulting accessible material and by relying on ideas which innumerable federal judges, law clerks, court employees, law professors, law students and Career Development Office personnel have expressed. For 2013–2015 data, see David Lat, The Current State of Clerkship Hiring: 5 Points Worth Noting, Above the Law (Apr. 28, 2015, 5:59 PM) https://abovethelaw.com/2015/04/the-current-state-of-clerkship-hiring-5-points-worth-noting [https://perma.cc/TLH7-FHUB]. For recent ideas, see Baude, supra note 1.

 [9]. The Administrative Office provided one day to apply, interview and offer. See Tobias, supra note 3, at 147; David Lat, Clerkship Hiring Is Getting Earlier and Earlier, Above the Law (Apr. 11, 2013, 2:25 PM) https://abovethelaw.com/2013/04/clerkship-hiring-is-getting-earlier-and-earlier [https://perma.cc/5V9P-UUY5]. In 2012, prominent law schools recommended that their 2L students apply in the spring, information on which many potential applicants capitalized. Other schools have provided similar advice since. Tobias, supra note 7, at 246.

 [10]. Exploding offers are ones that have short or no fuses. Many judges want freedom of action or oppose hiring plans because they function as cartels by limiting competition. See sources cited supra note 4.

 [11]. Memorandum from NALP Judicial Clerkship Section to Fed. Judges’ OSCAR Working Grp. 1 (Oct. 10, 2013) [hereinafter 2013 Memorandum], https://www.nalp.org/uploads/BoardReports/Judicial
ClerkshipSectionPerezNov2013.pdf [https://perma.cc/XS45-VTTS].

 [12]. Id. at 2–3; see also Tobias, supra note 7, at 246; Baude, supra note 1; Letter from Kerry Abrams et al. to the Members of the Federal Judiciary, supra note 4.

 [13]. 2013 Memorandum, supra note 11, at 1.

 [14]. Email from Laura Simon, OSCAR Program Manager, Admin. Office of the U.S. Courts, to Valerie L’Herrou, Dir. of Career Dev., Pub. Sector Careers, Univ. of Richmond Sch. of Law (Nov. 4, 2013) (on file with author); David Lat, Clerkship-Seeking 2Ls, Start Your Engines, Above the Law (Nov. 4, 2013, 2:03 PM), https://abovethelaw.com/2013/11/clerkship-seeking-2ls-start-your-engines [htt
ps://perma.cc/ULS8-4WB4].

 [15]. Memorandum from Judge John D. Bates, U.S. Courts Admin. Office Dir., to U.S. Judges (Jan. 13, 2014), [hereinafter Memorandum from Judge John Bates] https://oscar.uscourts.gov/assets/Federal_
Law_Clerk_Hiring-January_13_2014.pdf [https://perma.cc/DH3B-K2HK].

 [16]. Judge Bates adopted a proposal that gave rising second-year students OSCAR access in June, so judges may have hired after students’ first year. Id.

 [17]. Memorandum from Judge John Bates, supra note 15. I emphasize 2013 in this piece because the Administrative Office implemented comparatively few subsequent changes in federal law clerk employment. Federal Law Clerk Hiring Best Practices are:

  • Support a transparent recruitment process by maintaining OSCAR judge profiles that identify hiring practices and preferences. . . .
  • Consider coordinating hiring activities and efficiencies such as setting court-wide interview dates. Post interview dates in each OSCAR judge profile.
  • Use video conferencing or electronic face-to-face interviews . . . when feasible. . . .
  • Inform applicants of clerkship offer policies . . . [and grant reasonable time] to weigh [offers] against other viable offers. This does not prohibit [immediate acceptances].
  • Choose online[, fax,] or paper application methods rather than requiring applications submitted by email due to the hardship which emailing applications places on law schools and applicants.
  • Consider visiting law schools with a minority student population to share recruitment practices and insights . . . [that] may encourage more minority law students to [apply].

Federal Law Clerk Hiring Best Practices, OSCAR, https://oscar.uscourts.gov/hiring-practices [https://pe
rma.cc/L4GU-HTZH].

 [18]. Judge Bates implored his federal court colleagues to employ the online mechanism because OSCAR ensures transparency, eliminates paper, saves staff time, can increase diversity, and helps manage substantial numbers of applications with search and sort features. Memorandum from Judge John Bates, supra note 15.

 [19]. See, e.g., Lat, supra note 14; sources cited supra note 6.

 [20]. District court postings clearly outnumber appellate court postings. See sources cited supra note 6. But this is not surprising because the federal bench includes 677 active district judges and 179 active court of appeals judges. See Authorized Judgeships 8, https://www.uscourts.gov/sites/default/files/all
auth.pdf [https://perma.cc/2ULM-EKRZ].

 [21]. Hiring Plan, supra note 1; David Lat, Order in the Court, Order in the Court: The Law Clerk Hiring Plan Returns!, Above the Law (Mar. 1, 2018, 7:43 PM), https://abovethelaw.com/2018/03/order
-in-the-court-the-law-clerk-hiring-plan-returns/2 [https://perma.cc/R9KT-DYDE].

 [22]. Letter from Ad Hoc Comm. on Law Clerk Hiring to Fellow Judges (Feb. 28, 2018), https://oscar.uscourts.gov/_assets/Ad_Hoc_Committee_on_Law_Clerk_Hiring_Announcement [https://
perma.cc/9MGK-M3MT]; Judicial Clerkship Info for Career Services, NALP (Dec. 2019) https://www.nalp.org/judicialclerkshipinfoforcareerservices [https://perma.cc/V73Z-X2ZC]; Letter from Ad Hoc Comm. on Law Clerk Hiring to Fellow Judges (Dec. 2019), https://www.nalp.org/uploads/2019C
lerkshipHiring2ndPilotYearJudgesEmailDec19.pdf [https://perma.cc/FCS5-XAPY]. A small number of appellate courts leave the choice to each individual judge, the first three appeals courts supported earlier plans and the new one, and some judges of the Ninth Circuit have supported neither previous plans nor the pilot. Lat, supra note 21. Rather few appellate court judges follow the plan. Baude, supra note 1; Goldsmith, supra note 5.

 [23]. 2nd Pilot Year, supra note 1 (adding one day reading period); Baude, supra note 1; see also infra notes 25, 38 and accompanying text.

 [24]. For example, OSCAR proscribes “off-plan applications and requires those judges” to use word-of-mouth; some schools deny clerkship resources to off-plan students. Will Baude, Some Reluctant Skepticism About the New Law Clerk Hiring Plan, Reason: Volokh Conspiracy (Aug. 27, 2018, 10:36 AM), https://reason.com/2018/08/27/some-reluctant-skepticism-about-the-new [https://perma.cc/ES72-FDPG]; Aaron L. Nielson, D.C. Circuit Review – Reviewed: Why I Fear the D.C. Circuit’s Approach to Clerkship Hiring Is Misguided, Yale J. on Reg.: Notice & Comment (Aug. 24, 2018), https://www.yalejreg.com/nc/d-c-circuit-review-reviewed-why-i-fear-the-d-c-circuits-approach-to-clerk
ship-hiring-is-misguided [https://perma.cc/4PNB-DCZ2]; see also Letter from Kerry Abrams et al. to the Members of the Federal Judiciary, supra note 4. I rely substantially here on Professor Baude and Professor Goldsmith and my work advising students, but Mr. Lat, Professor Nielson, and I seem to share many of the views expressed.

 [25]. I rely substantially here on Professor Nielson, supra note 24, and Professor Goldsmith, supra note 5, but Professor Baude, Mr. Lat and I seem to share the views.

 [26]. Jack Goldsmith (@jacklgoldsmith), Twitter (July 15, 2019 11:47 AM) https://twitter.com/jac
klgoldsmith/status/1150839301929930752 [https://perma.cc/R5NH-L522] (claiming that more progressive students will be able to seek fewer clerkships, as more progressive judges follow the plan and hire later); see also Karen Sloan, Not Everyone Loves the Federal Clerk Hiring Plan, Law.com: Ahead of The Curve (Feb. 3, 2020, 9:00 PM), https://www.law.com/2020/02/03/ahead-of-the-curve-not-everyone-loves-the-federal-clerk-hiring-plan [https://perma.cc/RU3Y-EP5P]; Mark Joseph Stern, President of Harvard’s Federalist Society Brought a Gun to Zoom Class, Slate (Apr. 9, 2020), https://slate.com/news-and-politics/2020/04/chance-fletcher-federalist-society-harvard-gun.html [https://perma.cc/8XUV-7JJE]. Professor Baude surmises that the patterns can yield a regime which half the bench adopts and half rejects, so if students cluster by locale and ideologically, it could be rather stable but may frustrate those who wish to clerk for judges in each camp or many locales, and few would design this regime ex ante. Baude, supra note 24. Goldsmith and Baude predict the plan’s demise. Goldsmith, supra note 5; Baude, supra note 1. I rely here on Professor Goldsmith and Professor Baude, but I share their views.

 [27]. This season is uncertain and may only become clearer after mid-June and once the AO has scrutinized empirical data on the pilot. For later seasons, the judiciary must review the data and improve the pilot or craft a new plan. See Baude, supra note 1 (providing valuable suggestions for improving hiring after the pilot fails, which he predicts).

 [28]. The representative sample enhances earlier data’s value, because how most jurists will proceed this season remains unclear, as the nascent pilot and the 2014 advice are not mandatory, while many have hired later since 2013 and may still follow that and other earlier ideas.

 [29]. This hiring was predictable because their clerkships are competitive, prestigious and in desirable areas.

 [30]. There were also exceptions. For instance, Western Louisiana and Northern Florida judges had apparently hired clerks by May, while Minnesota and Eastern Michigan jurists seemingly had not employed by then.

 [31]. The Southern District of New York posted numerous judges’ measures; some jurists deployed rolling review but did not interview or offer until June 28 in 2013. Law Clerk Hiring Information, U.S. District Ct.: S. District N.Y., https://www.nysd.uscourts.gov/judges/law-clerk-hiring-information [https://perma.cc/Q8YS-EA5]; see Baude, supra note 24 (suggesting that requiring judges to post openings on the internet could help level the playing field).

 [32]. 28 U.S.C. § 371 (2018); see also David R. Stras & Ryan W. Scott, Are Senior Judges Unconstitutional?, 92 Cornell L. Rev. 453, 455 (2007); Joseph Goldstein, The Oldest Bench Ever, Slate (Jan. 18, 2011, 7:01 AM), https://slate.com/news-and-politics/2011/01/federal-judges-are-getting-older-and-more-often-senile.html [https://perma.cc/88CX-W6HV].

 [33]. 28 U.S.C. § 136 (2018). Magistrate judges and judges for territories, including Guam and the Virgin Islands, also hire. 28 U.S.C. § 631 (2018); 48 U.S.C. §§ 1424, 1612 (2018).

 [34]. Judicial Vacancies, U.S. Courts, https://www.uscourts.gov/judges-judgeships/judicial-vacancies [https://perma.cc/BLH7-YH33]; see Confirmation Listing, U.S. Courts, https://www.uscourt
s.gov/judges-judgeships/judicial-vacancies/confirmation-listing [https://perma.cc/GFW5-UEXD]; John Besche, YLS Students Speak About Clerking for Trump Appointees, Yale Daily News (Jan. 30, 2020, 11:54 PM), https://yaledailynews.com/blog/2020/01/30/progressive-law-students-speak-about-clerking-for-trump-appointees [https://perma.cc/TE4V-BTQA]. But see Hannah A. Klain et al., Harvard Law School: Its Time to Be Part of the Solution, Not the Problem, with Judicial Clerkships, Harv. Crimson (Feb. 5, 2019), https://www.thecrimson.com/article/2019/2/5/klain-kohnert-yourt-patel-judicial-clerkshi
ps [https://perma.cc/R3F6-JGMM]; Leah Litman, On Clerkships & Wasted Opportunities, Take Care (Dec. 23, 2019) https://takecareblog.com/blog/on-clerkships-and-wasted-opportunities [https://perma.cc/
7CF8-LUZF]; Stern, supra note 26.

 [35]. OSCAR Version 7: Limit of 100 Clerkship Applications, OSCAR Blog (Apr. 8, 2013, 11:10 AM), https://oscar.uscourts.gov/blog_post/_1/13/OSCAR_Version_7_Limit_of_100_Clerkship_Applic
ations [https://perma.cc/7N2Y-JE33].

 [36]. Numerous Career Development Offices maintain useful summaries of past students’ interview experiences. See Debra M. Strauss, Top Ten Tips for Judicial Clerkship Interviews, Above the Law (Jan. 22, 2015, 6:59 PM) https://abovethelaw.com/career-files/ten-tips-to-the-judicial-clerkship-intervie
w [https://perma.cc/89QK-65G2].

 [37]. For biographical data sources, see Judicial Yellow Book (Winter 2020); Forster-Long, The American Bench (2020).

 [38]. “If you have two young, male hot dogs [as clerks], you may [want one] who is a bit older, or female, or had a prior career.” Kozinski, supra note 2, at 1722. For an explanation as to why selecting the finest clerks is crucial for judges, see Patricia M. Wald, Selecting Law Clerks, 89 Mich. L. Rev. 152, 153 (1990).

 [39]. Kozinski, supra note 2, at 1716; see also Carl Tobias, Manuscript Selection AntiManifesto, 80 Cornell L. Rev. 529, 535 (1995); Wald, supra note 38, at 152, 156; supra note 10.

 [40]. Kozinski, supra note 2, at 1716; see also supra note 23 and accompanying text; Deborah Pines, Federal Judges Try to Fix Frantic Clerk Hiring, N.Y.L.J., June 14, 1993, at 26; Strauss, supra note 36. Many judges who hire early deploy this.

 [41]. Wald, supra note 38, at 156. This phenomenon resembles law review leveraging. Tobias, supra note 39, at 537–38.

 [42]. See generally Christopher Avery et al., The Market for Federal Judicial Law Clerks, 68 U. Chi. L. Rev. 793, 81320 (2001). Judges employ diverse measures to not offer. See Staci Zaretsky, Rejection Letter of the Day: You’re Not Prestigious Enough To Clerk In My Less-Than-Prestigious Court, Above the Law (Feb. 25, 2014), https://abovethelaw.com/2014/02/rejection-letter-of-the-day-youre-not-prestigious-enough-to-clerk-in-my-less-than-prestigious-court [https://perma.cc/X8Y8-AADS].

 [43]. See supra note 17. Many judges who rely on OSCAR post notices online that their slots are filled. Some who use paper applications do not. Students who have not received interviews by autumn can assume that most judges have hired.

 [44]. Hiring Plan, supra note 1; Nielson, supra note 24 (suggesting that forty-eight hours is insufficient time for making such an important decision).

Regulatory Entrepreneurship – Article by Elizabeth Pollman & Jordan M. Barry

From Volume 90, Number 3 (March 2017)
DOWNLOAD PDF

 
 
 This Article examines what we term “regulatory entrepreneurship”—pursuing a line of business in which changing the law is a significant part of the business plan. Regulatory entrepreneurship is not new, but it has become increasingly salient in recent years as companies from Airbnb to Tesla, and from DraftKings to Uber, have become agents of legal change. We document the tactics that companies have employed, including operating in legal gray areas, growing “too big to ban,” and mobilizing users for political support. Further, we theorize the business and law-related factors that foster regulatory entrepreneurship. Well-funded, scalable, and highly connected startup businesses with mass appeal have advantages, especially when they target state and local laws and litigate them in the political sphere instead of in court.

Finally, we predict that regulatory entrepreneurship will increase, driven by significant state and local policy issues, strong institutional support for startup companies, and continued technological progress that facilitates political mobilization. We explore how this could catalyze new coalitions, lower the cost of political participation, and improve policymaking. However, it could also lead to negative consequences when companies’ interests diverge from the public interest.


 

90_383

Strategic Rulemaking Disclosure – Article by Jennifer Nou and Edward H. Stiglitz

From Volume 89, Number 4 (May 2016)
DOWNLOAD PDF

 

Congressional enactments and executive orders instruct agencies to publish their anticipated rules in what is known as the Unified Agenda. The Agenda’s stated purpose is to ensure that political actors can monitor regulatory development. Agencies have come under fire in recent years, however, for conspicuous omissions and irregularities. Critics allege that agencies hide their regulations from the public strategically, that is, to thwart potential political opposition. Others contend that such behavior is benign, perhaps the inevitable result of changing internal priorities or unforeseen events.

To examine these competing hypotheses, this Article uses a new dataset spanning over thirty years of rulemaking (1983–2014). Uniquely, the dataset is drawn directly from the Federal Register. The resulting findings reveal that agencies substantially underreport their rulemaking activities—about 70 percent of their proposed rules do not appear on the Unified Agenda before publication. Importantly, agencies also appear to disclose strategically with respect to Congress, though not with respect to the president. The Unified Agenda is thus not a successful tool for Congress to monitor and influence regulatory development. The results suggest that legislative, not executive, innovations may help to augment public participation and democratic oversight, though the net effects of more transparency remain uncertain. The findings also raise further inquiries, such as why Congress does not render disclosure requirements judicially enforceable.


 

89_733